New Rules of Sociological Method - Anthony Giddens - E-Book

New Rules of Sociological Method E-Book

Anthony Giddens

0,0
20,40 €

-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

This is a new and revised edition of a book which has already established itself as a basic text in social theory. The first section of the work provides a concise critical analysis of some leading schools of thought in social philosophy, giving particular attention to phenomenology, ethnomethodology and Wittgensteinian thought. Giddens concentrates primarily upon the implications of these various perspectives for an account of human action and its intelligibility. An `action approach' on its own, however, will not do; in human social life, action and structure presuppose one another. The author therefore moves on to provide a series of concepts relevant to understanding the production and reproduction of society. The book concludes with a succinct statement of some `new rules of sociological method'. Representing the first, and most trenchant, exposition of the principles of structuration theory, this edition also contains a substantial new Introduction in which Giddens replies to some of the more persistent criticisms made of the original version and also addresses some important issues originally discussed only in a cursory way.

Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:

Android
iOS
von Legimi
zertifizierten E-Readern

Seitenzahl: 342

Veröffentlichungsjahr: 2013

Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



New Rules of Sociological Method

A Positive Critique of Interpretative Sociologies

Anthony Giddens

Second Edition

Polity Press

Copyright © Anthony Giddens 1993

The right of Anthony Giddens to be identified as author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.

First published by Hutchinson, 1976.

Second, revised edition first published in 1993 by Polity Press in association with Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

Reprinted 1994, 1997, 2005, 2007

Polity Press 65 Bridge Street Cambridge CB2 1UR, UK

Polity Press 350 Main Street Malden, MA 02148, USA

All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher.

Except in the United States of America, this book is sold subject to the condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re-sold, hired out, or otherwise circulated without the publisher’s prior consent in any form of binding or cover other than that in which it is published and without a similar condition including this condition being imposed on the subsequent purchaser.

ISBN: 978-0-7456-1116-7

ISBN: 978-0-7456-1117-4 (pbk)

ISBN: 978-0-7456-6652-5 (eBook)

A CIP catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

Typeset in 11 on 13 pt Times by Graphicraft Typesetters Ltd, Hong Kong

Printed and bound in Great Britain by Marston Book Services Limited, Oxford

This book is printed on acid-free paper.

For further information on Polity, visit our website: www.polity.co.uk

Contents

Preface

Introduction to the Second Edition

Introduction to the First Edition

1    Some Schools of Social Theory and Philosophy

Existential phenomenology: Schutz

Ethnomethodology

Post-Wittgensteinian philosophy: Winch

Summary: the significance of interpretative sociologies

Hermeneutics and critical theory: Gadamer, Apel, Habermas

2    Agency, Act-identifications and Communicative Intent

Problems of agency

Intentions and projects

The identification of acts

The rationalization of action

Meaning and communicative intent

3    The Production and Reproduction of Social Life

Order, power, conflict: Durkheim and Parsons

Order, power, conflict: Marx

The production of communication as ‘meaningful’

Moral orders of interaction

Relations of power in interaction

Rationalization and reflexivity

The motivation of action

The production and reproduction of structure

Summary

4    The Form of Explanatory Accounts

Positivistic dilemmas

Later developments: Popper and Kuhn

Science and non-science

Relativism and hermeneutic analysis

The problem of adequacy

Conclusion: Some New Rules of Sociological Method

Notes

Index

Preface

This study is only intended as one part of a more embracing project. While it can of course be read as a self-contained work, it touches upon various issues that are not dealt with in a detailed way, but which are vital to my project as a whole. This latter involves three overlapping concerns. One is to develop a critical approach to the development of nineteenth-century social theory, and its subsequent incorporation as the institutionalized and professionalized ‘disciplines’ of ‘sociology’, ‘anthropology’ and ‘political science’ in the course of the twentieth century. Another is to trace out some of the main themes in nineteenth-century social thought which became built into theories of the formation of the advanced societies and subject these to critique. The third is to elaborate upon, and similarly to begin a reconstruction of, problems raised by the – always troubling – character of the social sciences as concerned with, as a ‘subject-matter’, what those ‘sciences’ themselves presuppose: human social activity and intersubjectivity. This book is proposed as a contribution to the last of these three. But any such discussion bursts the bounds of this sort of conceptual container, and has immediate implications for work in the other areas. As a single project, they are tied together as an endeavour to construct a critical analysis of the legacy of the social theory of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries for the contemporary period.

This book is about ‘method’ in the sense in which social philosophers characteristically employ the term – the sense in which Durkheim used it in his Rules of Sociological Method. That is to say, it is not a guide to ‘how to do practical research’, and does not offer any specific research proposals. It is primarily an exercise in clarification of logical issues. I have subtitled the study a ‘positive critique’ of ‘interpretative sociologies’. Anyone who reads on will see that this does not mean ‘positivistic’. I use it only to mean ‘sympathetic’ or ‘constructive’: the sense that predates Comte’s translation of the term into a definite philosophy of social and natural science. ‘Interpretative sociologies’ is something of a misnomer for the schools of thought that appear in the first chapter, since some of the authors whose work is discussed there are anxious to separate what they have to say from ‘sociology’. I use the term only because there is no other readily available one, to group together a series of writings that have certain shared concerns with ‘meaningful action’.

The themes of this study are that social theory must incorporate a treatment of action as rationalized conduct ordered reflexively by human agents, and must grasp the significance of language as the practical medium whereby this is made possible. The implications of these notions are profound, and the book is confined to tracing through only some of them. Anyone who recognizes that self-reflection, as mediated linguistically, is integral to the characterization of human social conduct must acknowledge that such holds also for his or her own activities as a social ‘analyst’, ‘researcher’, etc. I think it correct to say, moreover, that theories produced in the social sciences are not just ‘meaning frames’ in their own right, but also constitute moral interventions in the social life whose conditions of existence they seek to clarify.

Introduction to the Second Edition

Quite a number of years have passed since this book first saw the light of day, but I hope it has not lost its relevance to current problems of social theory. In New Rules I deal with a number of forms of interpretative sociology, as well as with certain more central sociological traditions. When I wrote it, I regarded the book – and continue to do so today – as a ‘dialogic critique’ of the forms of social and philosophical thought which it addresses. That is, it is a critical engagement with ideas that I see as of essential importance, but which for one reason or another were not adequately developed in the perspectives from which they originally sprang. Some have seen such a strategy as a misplaced eclecticism, but I consider such dialogic critique as the very life-blood of fruitful conceptual development in social theory.

New Rules of Sociological Method dovetails with other ‘positive critiques’ which I sought to provide in elaborating the basic tenets of structuration theory. In complementary writings that I undertook at about the same period, I addressed approaches to social analysis either left aside, or treated only in a marginal way, in New Rules. Such approaches included naturalistic sociology – a term which I now think of as preferable to the more diffuse and ambiguous label, ‘positivism’ – functionalism, structuralism and ‘post-structuralism’. The Constitution of Society (1984) established a more comprehensive framework for the notion of structuration than was available in New Rules, but did not supplant it.1New Rules makes an independent statement about questions of agency, structure and social transformation; its distinctive concentration is upon the nature of ‘action’ and the implications of an analysis of action for the logic of social science.

The debates have moved on over the period since New Rules was originally published, but in revising the text I have found little of substance that I think it necessary to abandon or reformulate. The work of Talcott Parsons still has its adherents and, as filtered through the writings of Niklas Luhmann and others, remains influential; but it no longer has the central position it once held. Phenomenological notions are not as widely drawn upon now as they were at the time, while post-structuralism, in its different guises, has increased its importance and has become allied to conceptions of post-modernism. I do not feel, however, that these changes make any substantial difference to the standpoint I developed in this study, which retains its validity.

New Rules has attracted its own share of critiques, some positive and others more destructive in impetus. I have responded to such criticism in a variety of places and shall not cover the same ground again here. Let me concentrate upon two issues only: whether or not the idea of the ‘duality of structure’, vital to structuration theory, merges levels of social life that should be kept apart; and whether the distinction between the ‘single hermeneutic’ of natural science and the ‘double hermeneutic’ of the social sciences should be sustained. The literature subsequent to the publication of New Rules contains many discussions of these problems. For purposes of simplicity, I shall focus upon those offered by Nicos Mouzelis in respect of the first question, and Hans Harbers and Gerard de Vries in respect of the second.2

Many critics have accepted the objections I made against the concept of structure as ordinarily used in sociology. Seen as ‘fixed’ and, in Durkheimian fashion, as ‘external’ to social actors, it appears as a constraint upon action, rather than also as enabling. It is to grasp this double character that I introduced the notion of the duality of structure. What are some of the objections that might be levelled against it? They include the following.

1It may be true that actors routinely draw upon rules and resources, and thereby reproduce them, in the course of their day-to-day activities. Surely, however; such an orientation to rules and resources is not the only, or even the predominant, one they have? For, as Mouzelis puts it, ‘Actors often distance themselves from rules and resources, in order to question them, or in order to build theories about them, or – even more importantly – in order to devise strategies for either their maintenance or their transformation.’3

2Hence it follows that the idea of the duality of structure cannot properly account for the constitution or reproduction of social systems. Rules and resources are reproduced not only in the context of their practical use, but also where actors ‘distance’ themselves from them in order to treat them in a strategic way. When such a circumstance applies, the concept of the duality of structure is quite inappropriate. Instead, perhaps, we should speak of a dualism, because the individual, the ‘subject’, confronts rules and resources as ‘objects’ in the social environment.

3These comments bear directly upon distinctions between micro- and macro-analysis in the social sciences. Although not discussed directly in New Rules, the micro/macro differentiation, as ordinarily understood, is something which I place in question. However, if we try to do without it, the critic asserts, the result is an illegitimate reductionism. Social systems have many structural properties which cannot be understood in terms of the actions of situated individuals. Micro- and macro-analysis are not mutually exclusive; each in fact requires the other, but they have to be kept apart.

4The idea of the duality of structure cannot cope with action oriented to large- rather than small-scale contexts. For instance, it may work well when one considers an everyday conversation between two people in the street, but does not fit a situation where, say, a group of heads of state meet to take decisions affecting millions. The former situation, it might be said , is inconsequential in its implications for larger social orders, while the latter affects such orders in a direct and comprehensive way. In structuration theory there is an ‘identification’ of agency with ‘micro-subjects which, by the routine use of rules and resources, contribute to the reproduction of the institutional order. Macro action is neglected – both the type of action that results from the incumbency of authority positions … as well as that which results from the variable ability of individual subjects to group together in order to defend, maintain, or transform rules and resources.’4

5The Durkheimian notions of externality and constraint need to be sustained, albeit perhaps not in the form in which Durkheim himself expressed them. There are degrees or levels involved; what is external and constraining for one individual may be much less so for another. This point connects with the previous ones, for it means recognizing that social life is hierarchical – rather than speaking of ‘the individual’ confronting ‘society’, we should acknowledge a multiplicity of levels of social organization, with varying degrees of disjunction between them.

In responding to such observations, let me first of all expand upon why I developed the concept of duality of structure. I did so in order to contest two main types of dualism. One is that found among pre-existing theoretical perspectives. Interpretative sociologies, such as those discussed in New Rules, as I have put it elsewhere, are ‘strong on action, but weak on structure’. They see human beings as purposive agents, who are aware of themselves as such and have reasons for what they do; but they have little means of coping with issues which quite rightly bulk large in functionalist and structural approaches – problems of constraint, power and large-scale social organization. This second group of approaches, on the other hand, while ‘strong on structure’, has been ‘weak on action’. Agents are treated as if they were inert and inept – the playthings of forces larger than themselves.

In breaking away from such a dualism of theoretical perspectives, the analysis developed in New Rules also rejects the dualism of ‘the individual’ and ‘society’. Neither forms a proper starting-point for theoretical reflection; instead the focus is upon reproduced practices. It is important, however, to be clear about what discarding the dualism of ‘the individual’/‘society’ means. It emphatically does not mean denying that there are social systems and forms of collectivity which have their own distinct structural properties. Nor does it imply that those properties are somehow ‘contained’ in the actions of each situated individual. To challenge the dualism of the individual and society is to insist that each should be deconstructed.

Since ‘the individual’ has corporeal existence, the concept might seem unproblematic. Yet an individual is not a body and even the notion of the body, in relation to the acting self, turns out to be complex. To speak of an individual is to speak not just of a ‘subject’, but also of an agent; the idea of action (as Talcott Parsons always stressed) is thus inevitably a central one. Moreover – and this is crucial – action is not simply a quality of the individual but is, equally, the stuff of social organization or collective life as well. Most sociologists, including even many working within frameworks of interpretative sociology, have failed to recognize that social theory, no matter how ‘macro’ its concerns, demands a sophisticated understanding of agency and the agent just as much as it does an account of the complexities of society. It is precisely such an understanding that New Rules seeks to develop.

The concept of the duality of structure is bound up with the logic of social analysis; it does not, in and of itself, offer any generalizations about the conditions of social reproduction/ transformation. This point is fundamental, because otherwise a structurationist view would indeed be open to the charge of reductionism. To say that the production and reproduction of social life are one and the same thing takes no position at all about the conditions of stability or change in concrete conditions of social activity. Rather, it is to say that neither on the level of logic, nor in our practical day-to-day lives, can we step outside the flow of action, whether such action contributes to the most rigid of social institutions or to the most radical forms of social change.

These things having been said, I can comment upon points 1-5 in sequence. Point 1 both misunderstands the notion of duality of structure and presumes too primitive a concept of reflexivity. All actors are social theorists, and must be so to be social agents at all. The conventions which are drawn upon in the organization of social life are never ‘blind habits’. One of the distinctive contributions of phenomenology, and particularly of ethnomethodology, has been to show that (1) the conduct of social life continually involves ‘theorizing’ and (2) even the most enduring of habits, or the most unshakeable of social norms, involves continual and detailed reflexive attention. Routinization is of elemental importance in social life; but all routines, all the time, are contingent and potentially fragile accomplishments.

Individuals in all forms of society ‘distance themselves’ from rules and resources, approach them strategically and so forth. In some respects, for reasons just noted, this is the condition of even the most regularized modes of social reproduction. No matter how traditional a context of action, for example, tradition is chronically interpreted, reinterpreted, generalized about, as the very means whereby it is ‘done’. Of course, all moments of reflexive attention themselves draw upon, and reconstitute, rules and resources; to repeat, there can be no stepping outside of the flow of action.

The sort of ‘distancing’ Mouzelis has in mind, however, is particularly evident in social circumstances where the hold of tradition has become attenuated. A useful distinction can be drawn here between reflexivity, as a quality of human action as a whole, and institutional reflexivity, as an historical phenomenon. Institutional reflexivity refers to the institutionalization of an investigative and calculative attitude towards generalized conditions of system reproduction; it both stimulates and reflects a decline in traditional ways of doing things. It is also associated with the generation of power (understood as transformative capacity). The expansion of institutional reflexivity stands behind the proliferation of organizations in circumstances of modernity, including organizations of global scope.5

So far as point 2 goes, I should reaffirm that the duality of structure ‘accounts for’ nothing. It has explanatory value only when we consider real historical situations of some sort. The ‘duality’ of the duality of structure concerns the dependence of action and structure, taken as a logical assertion, but it certainly does not involve a merging of the situated actor with the collectivity. Much better here, indeed, to speak of a hierarchy rather than the sustaining of a dualism: there are many modes of interconnection between individuals and collectivities. It is perfectly obvious that every situated actor faces an environment of action which has an ‘objectivity’ for him or her in a quasi-Durkheimian sense.

As for points 3 and 4, the distinction between micro- and macro-analysis is not a very useful one in social science, at least in some of the ways in which it is ordinarily understood. It is especially misleading if seen itself as a dualism – where ‘micro-situations’ are those to which a notion of agency is appropriate, whereas ‘macro-situations’ are those over which individuals have no control.6 What is important is to consider the ties, as well as the disjunctions, between situations of co-presence and ‘mediated connections’ between individuals and collectivities of various types. It is just not the case that what Mouzelis calls ‘macro action’ is left aside in structuration theory. ‘Macro action’, however, for the reasons he gives, is not the same as lack of co-presence: here the phenomenon of differential power is usually central. A small number of individuals meeting together may enact policies that have very extensive consequences. Macro-action of this sort is even more pervasive than Mouzelis implies, because it is by no means limited to conscious processes of decision-making; large-scale systems of power are reproduced just as strongly in more routinized circumstances of co-present interaction.

As for point 5, social life, particularly in conditions of modernity, does involve multiple levels of collective activity. Far from being inconsistent with the views set out in New Rules, such an observation is entirely in line with them. ‘Externality’ and ‘constraint’ cannot be seen, as Durkheim thought, as general characteristics of ‘social facts’. ‘Constraint’ takes several forms, some of which again concern the phenomenon of differential power. The ‘externality’ of social facts does not define them as social facts, but instead directs attention to various different properties/contexts/levels of the environments of action of situated individuals.

In structuration theory, the concept of ‘structure’ presumes that of ‘system’: it is only social systems or collectivities which have structural properties. Structure derives above all from regularized practices and is hence closely tied to institutionalization; structure gives form to totalizing influences in social life. Is it then in the end misleading to try to illuminate the conception of the duality of structure by reference to language use? It is misleading, I think, if we see language as a closed and homogeneous entity. Rather, we should conceive of language as a fragmented and diverse array of practices, contexts and modes of collective organization. As I stress in the text, the idea of Lévi-Strauss, that ‘society is like a language’, should be resisted strongly; but the study of language certainly helps cast light upon some basic characteristics of social activity as a whole.

All this having been said, the critic may still feel worried or dissatisfied. For is there not a long distance between ‘everyday practices’, the situated interaction of individuals, and the properties of the large-scale, even global, social systems that influence so much of modern social life? How could the former in any way be the medium of the reproduction of the structural properties of the latter? One response to this question would be to say that, as a result of current globalizing trends, there actually are very important respects in which everyday activities connect to global outcomes and vice versa. In the global economy, for example, local purchasing decisions affect, and serve to constitute, economic orders which in turn act back upon subsequent decisions. The type of food a person eats is globally consequential in respect of global ecology. On a somewhat less encompassing level, the way in which a man looks at a woman may be a constituting element of deeply engrained structures of gender power. The reproduction/transformation of globalizing systems is implicated in a whole variety of day-to-day decisions and acts.

Deconstructing ‘society’, however, means recognizing the basic significance of diversity, context and history. Processes of empirical social reproduction intersect with one another in many different ways in relation to their time-space ‘stretch’, to the generation and distribution of power, and to institutional reflexivity. The proper locus for the study of social reproduction is in the immediate process of the constituting of interaction, for all social life is an active accomplishment; and every moment of social life bears the imprint of the totality. ‘The totality’, however, is not an inclusive, bounded ‘society’, but a composite of diverse totalizing orders and impulsions.

Institutional reflexivity – this notion connects the analysis of modernity with the more generalized idea of the double hermeneutic. The ‘double’ of the ‘double hermeneutic’ again implies a duality: the ‘findings’ of social science do not remain insulated from the ‘subject-matter’ to which they refer, but consistently re-enter and reshape it. It is of the first importance to emphasize that what is at issue here is not the existence of feed-back mechanisms. On the contrary, the intrusion of concepts and knowledge-claims back into the universe of events they were coined to describe produces an essential erraticism. The double hermeneutic is thus intrinsically involved in the dislocated, fragmenting nature of modernity as such, particularly in the phase of ‘high modernity’.7

Many implications flow from this observation, but I shall consider the thesis of the double hermeneutic here only from the point of view of recent debates in the philosophy and sociology of science. Such debates have their origins in the by-now accepted observation that natural science has hermeneutic traits. As discussed in New Rules, the old differentiation between Verstehen and Erklären has become problematic; the idea that natural science deals only, or even primarily, in law-like generalization belongs to a view of scientific activity which has now largely become abandoned. As Karen Knorr-Cetina puts it, ‘Natural science investigation is grounded in the same kind of situational logic and marked by the same kind of indexical reasoning which we used to associate with the symbolic and interactional character of the social world.’8

Such conclusions have been reached as a result of sociological studies of science rather than philosophical interpretation. Thus experimentation, long considered the bedrock of scientific knowledge, has been studied as a process of the translation and construction of contextual information. But is this a ‘single hermeneutic’ which can be differentiated from the double hermeneutic of natural science? Some, including Knorr-Cetina, claim not. This distinction, she says, depends upon two assumptions: that human beings possess ‘causal agency’ not found in nature; and that, in the social world, there is a distinctive means, conscious appropriation, whereby causal agency is triggered. Neither is justified. The first rests upon too unsophisticated a notion of natural causality, for objects in the natural world may also be said to possess causal powers. The second ignores the fact that there are equivalent, if not directly parallel, triggering mechanisms for the reception of information in the world of nature.

Harbers and de Vries suggest that these conflicting views of the double hermeneutic can be looked at in the light of empirical evidence. Knorr-Cetina bases her thesis upon historical and sociological studies of natural science. Why not consider in a direct way the influence of social science within broader frameworks of knowledge and action? According to them, the thesis of the double hermeneutic presumes two hypotheses: that where the common-sense interpretations constituting social phenomena become the subject of historical change, interpretations offered within the social sciences will change correspondingly; and that novel concepts or findings developed within social science will have to be defended not only within the sociological community but in relation to a ‘common-sense forum of lay individuals’. The notion of the double hermeneutic implies that, in contrast to the situation in natural science, sociologists have a ‘scientific’, rather than only civic, obligation to present their ideas to a lay audience.9 Harbers and de Vries examine these hypotheses by looking at developments in education in The Netherlands.

Sociologists have long been involved in documenting unequal educational opportunities. Many projects were established in different countries from the 1950s onwards in order to uncover the factors influencing such inequalities. The Dutch Project on Talents was one of these, the work of a group of eleven social investigators. The idea of the research was to study the large reserve of ‘unused talents’ believed to exist. In other words, it was thought that many children from poorer backgrounds were qualified for advanced levels of secondary education, but were not to be found in the appropriate schools. The results did not conform to this expectation. Children attended schools which matched their abilities; the relative under-representation of children from underprivileged backgrounds was not because of misdirected decisions about type of school after primary education. The children had already lagged behind in primary school.

These conclusions were at first accepted by most educational authorities and government policy became based on them. Subsequently, however, another researcher published a book using new calculations derived from the same data. Using a different concept of ‘talent’, he concluded that a reserve of unusual talents did indeed exist. The original Project on Talents had been carried out within a definite framework of assumptions corresponding to a popular view of what a ‘meritocracy’ is. The second researcher attacked those assumptions, and proposed not only a different view of educational equality but a different practical orientation to reducing it. His concepts and findings contributed to a dissolution of the ‘meritocratic consensus’ that previously existed. In turn, the sociology of education produced new definitions of research problems and became divided into a number of opposing perspectives. These then in their turn were filtered back into public debates on educational policy issues.

Harbers and de Vries suggest that their study provides a concrete example of the double hermeneutic: public attitudes on education were altered by, and helped alter, processes of social research. Where the ‘theoretical style’ of research work is consonant with widely held lay assumptions, they say, commonsense assumptions remain unnoticed by all parties. In such a situation, the sociological investigator can appear as an ‘autonomous scientist’, much like the natural scientist. Where a variety of dissident opinions exists among the lay public, however, claims about analyses of social phenomena have to be put forward and defended simultaneously in different forums. They conclude:

social scientists are dependent upon common sense thinking in a way which is strikingly different from the relation between common sense and scientific knowledge in the natural sciences. Whereas, of course, in the latter ideas, concepts, metaphors, etcetera may be adopted from non-scientific traditions and, hence, common sense thinking may serve as a resource, common sense interpretations set limits to the social sciences and constrain their cognitive development along the lines set out in the hypotheses we have formulated.10

The view of Harbers and de Vries has been criticized by William Lynch, who defends a view close to that of Knorr-Cetina.11 The social and natural sciences are after all not so different; but to see this we must concentrate more upon natural than social science. Thus an interaction between accounts of a subject-matter and ‘responses’ from that subject-matter occurs in the natural as well as the social world. In social life, actors’ accounts are often, even normally, ‘represented’ – some people, who remain silent, are spoken for by others. The same happens in natural science where scientists or lay actors ‘speak for’ the natural world. Similarly, the causal order of natural reality is altered by accounts imposed on it. For the natural world is not an inert, pre-given object, but is itself ‘constituted’ by the accounts scientists and lay agents provide.

Consider the phenomenon of deductive-nomological laws in the natural sciences. Such laws, Lynch says, ‘do not hold in the real world’. Rather, they depend upon elaborate interventions which scientists make into the natural order to establish the conditions under which such laws can be ‘seen to hold’. To ‘extend’ such laws outside the laboratory usually implies constructing conditions in which law-like behaviour can be ‘appropriately manifested’. Such laws ‘depend for their applicability on closed conditions that never fully obtain and require intervention and manipulation for their demonstration’.12

If natural scientists are able to claim greater autonomy than their counterparts in the social sciences, this is largely because of the degree to which a culture favourable to scientific claims has developed in modern societies. A great deal of work has gone into ensuring that natural scientists are less accountable than their social-scientific colleagues for their epistemic choices. Focusing on a double hermeneutic only in social science, therefore, reinforces a well-established tendency to obscure the cognitive and practical impact which natural science has upon the lives of lay individuals. The double hermeneutic, as applied specifically to social science, proscribes ‘empirical examination of past lay constraints on natural scientific development and, potentially, further interventions in issues for which the public might claim to have a stake’.13

To assess the validity of these ideas it is necessary to go over some of the ground covered in New Rules about the concept of the double hermeneutic – in respect not just of the meaning of ‘double’ but also of that of ‘hermeneutic’. The idea of the double hermeneutic is partly a logical and partly an empirical one. All social science is irretrievably hermeneutic in the sense that to be able to describe ‘what someone is doing’ in any given context means knowing what the agent or agents themselves know, and apply, in the constitution of their activities. It is being able (in principle) to ‘go on’ – mutual knowledge shared by participants and social-scientific observers. The hermeneutic element involved here does not have a parallel in natural science, which does not deal with knowledgeable agents in such a way – even in the case of most animal behaviour.

This is the logical side of the double hermeneutic. Lay actors are concept-bearing beings, whose concepts enter constitutively into what they do; the concepts of social science cannot be kept insulated from their potential appropriation and incorporation within everyday action. The empirical side concerns institutional reflexivity, a phenomenon which, as noted previously, becomes particularly pervasive with the maturation of the modern social order. The social sciences are deeply involved in the institutional reflexivity of modernity, although they far from exhaust it. As an empirical phenomenon, institutional reflexivity lends itself to research study, although in this regard certain provisos must be made. There is no way of standing wholly apart from reflexivity, since the social-scientific observer, by making her or his results public, relinquishes control over them. The ambition of blunting institutional reflexivity by means of preventing the self-fulfilling or self-negating prophecy, as New Rules makes clear, is a futile one; not because research cannot sometimes take account of them, but because they are seen as contaminations of the research process, rather than as intrinsic to the relation between social science and its ‘subject-matter’.

Is there any virtue in the sort of study carried out by Harbers and de Vries? There is, I think, as a case-study of certain processes of institutional reflexivity; but fresh empirical research is not needed, in my view, to document that the double hermeneutic actually exists. Institutional reflexivity is so central to modernity that a myriad of examples of it could be offered. The double hermeneutic is much more complex, and less narrowly bounded, than Harbers and de Vries assume in their formulation. There is no necessary match between changing common-sense interpretations of social phenomena and the ideas and theories of social science. Many different connections and oppositions between these are possible. The findings of social science do, in my view, have to be defended vis-à-vis those whose activities they cover, and others also; but this is primarily an ethical/political issue, because of the claim to ‘know better’ than lay agents themselves why things happen as they do.

These considerations do not resolve the question of whether there is a double hermeneutic in natural science. If such were the case, we should have a new version of the ‘unity of the sciences’, albeit one which differs greatly from the old naturalistic view. Since New Rules was written, constructivist and ethnomethodological accounts of natural science have developed apace and, apart perhaps from their more eccentric fringes, have contributed much to the emergence of a sophisticated sociological understanding of science. I do not believe, however, that they compromise the views set out here. The ‘single hermeneutic’ of science should not be equated with its autonomy in respect of lay beliefs and activities. Here we must insist upon the distinction between mutual knowledge and common sense. Scientific ideas may derive from common-sense beliefs and concepts, as well as place them in question. Sometimes such beliefs act as stimulants and at other times as constraints upon natural science investigations. The concepts and findings of the natural sciences do not remain separate from the social world, or from interventions, conceptual and technological, which human beings make into the world of nature. The hermeneutics of natural science, and the associated activities of the construction of investigatory procedures, are not confined to the interplay of technical meanings. Since Gödel, we know that even the most formal systems of mathematics presume ‘outside’ concepts, and obviously ordinary language is the medium by which scientific procedures and discussions are produced and carried on. It is certainly not true that the thesis of the double hermeneutic as specific to social science implies a prohibition upon interactions between science and lay culture.

The relation between the natural scientist and his or her field of investigation, however, is neither constituted nor mediated by mutual knowledge, in the way I have defined that term – unlike the relations between scientists themselves or between them and the lay public. This is why the double hermeneutic has peculiar reference to the social sciences. It is not affected by the fact that, in respect of both natural and social science, some people speak on account of those who remain silent or inarticulate. Nor is the position affected by constructivism, even in its more radical guises. For no one suggests that it is the natural world which constructs accounts of itself.

One consequence of the double hermeneutic is that original ideas and findings in social science tend to ‘disappear’ to the degree to which they are incorporated within the familiar components of practical activities. This is one of the main reasons why social science does not have parallel ‘technological’ applications to natural science, and why it typically sustains less prestige in the public eye than the natural sciences do. For the most interesting and challenging ideas are precisely those most likely to be seized upon in lay domains – although, to emphasize the point again, with many differing possible outcomes. Superficially, modern civilization seems almost wholly dominated by natural science; the social sciences are very much the poor relations, which hardly get a look in. In reality, the impact of social science – understood in the widest possible way, as systematic and informed reflection upon the conditions of social activity – is of core significance to modern institutions, which are unthinkable without it.

In revising the text of the book, I have not sought to make major changes. Nor have I added any substantially new sections, but have limited myself to making stylistic alterations and eliminating one or two paragraphs referring to material that has now become excessively dated. I have taken out about half of the notes from the original edition, but have not tried to update those that remain; the bibliography from the first edition has also been omitted.

Introduction to the First Edition

As we know them today, the social sciences were shaped by the spectacular advances of natural science and technology in the late eighteenth and the nineteenth centuries. I say this bluntly, in awareness of the complexities which it conceals. It would certainly not be true to say that the successes of human beings in seemingly mastering nature intellectually in science, and materially in technology, were adopted uncritically as forming a model for social thought. Throughout the nineteenth century, idealism in social philosophy and romanticism in literature, in their various guises, maintained their distance from the intellectual stand-points fostered by the natural sciences, and normally expressed deep hostility to the spread of machine technology. But for the most part, authors within these traditions were as sceptical of the possibility of creating a science of society as they were distrustful of the claims of the sciences of nature, and their views served as no more than a critical foil to the much more influential writings of those who sought to create just such a science. Mentioning just one or two figures in isolation is risky, but I think it reasonable to regard Comte and Marx as the pre-eminent influences upon the subsequent development of the social sciences (I shall use this term primarily to refer to sociology and anthropology, but shall also on occasion make reference to economics and to history). Comte’s influence is fundamental since, as projected through Durkheim’s writings, his conception of sociological method can readily be traced through to some of the basic themes of ‘academic sociology’ and anthropology in the twentieth century. Following Marx’s own scornful dismissal of Comte, Marxism set itself against those streams of social theory connected to the emphases of the former author. Comte’s formulation of the idea of a natural science of society was actually a sophisticated one, as anyone can check for himself by glancing through no more than a few pages of the Philosophie Positive, even if it lacked the subtleties (and, it must be said, some of the logical difficulties) of Marx’s work, informed as the latter was by a transposed Hegelian dialectic. Both Comte and Marx wrote in the shadow of the triumphs of natural science, and both regarded the extension of science to the study of human conduct in society as a direct outcome of the progressive march of human understanding towards humanity itself.