Supplements To The Second Book.
Supplements to the Third Book.
Supplements to the Fourth Book.
Appendix.
Supplements To The Second Book.
Chapter XXI. Retrospect and More
General View.If theintellectwere not
of a subordinate nature, as the two preceding chapters show, then
everything which takes place without it,i.e., without intervention of the
idea, such as reproduction, the development and maintenance of the
organism, the healing of wounds, the restoration or vicarious
supplementing of mutilated parts, the salutary crisis in diseases,
the works of the mechanical skill of animals, and the performances
of instinct would not be done so infinitely better and more
perfectly than what takes place with the assistance of intellect,
all conscious and intentional achievements of men, which compared
with the former are mere bungling. In generalnaturesignifies that which operates,
acts, performs without the assistance of the intellect. Now, that
this is really identical with what we find in ourselves aswillis the general theme of this
second book, and also of the essay, “Ueber den
Willen in der Natur.” The possibility of this
fundamental knowledge depends upon the fact thatin usthe will is directly lighted by
the intellect, which here appears as self-consciousness; otherwise
we could just as little arrive at a fuller knowledge of itwithin usas without us, and must for
ever stop at inscrutable forces of nature. We have to [pg 002]
abstract from the assistance of theintellectif we wish to comprehend the
nature of the will in itself, and thereby, as far as is possible,
penetrate to the inner being of nature.On this account, it may be remarked in passing, my direct
antipode among philosophers is Anaxagoras; for he assumed
arbitrarily as that which is first and original, from which
everything proceeds, a νους, an intelligence, a subject of ideas,
and he is regarded as the first who promulgated such a view.
According to him the world existed earlier in the mere idea than in
itself; while according to me it is the unconsciouswillwhich constitutes the reality of
things, and its development must have advanced very far before it
finally attains, in the animal consciousness, to the idea and
intelligence; so that, according to me, thought appears as the very
last. However, according to the testimony of Aristotle (Metaph., i. 4), Anaxagoras himself did
not know how to begin much with his νους, but merely set it up, and
then left it standing like a painted saint at the entrance, without
making use of it in his development of nature, except in cases of
need, when he did not know how else to help himself. All
physico-theology is a carrying out of the error opposed to the
truth expressed at the beginning of this chapter—the error that the
most perfect form of the origin of things is that which is brought
about by means of anintellect.
Therefore it draws a bolt against all deep exploration of
nature.From the time of Socrates down to our own time, we find that
the chief subject of the ceaseless disputations of the philosophers
has been thatens rationis,
calledsoul. We see the most of
them assert its immortality, that is to say, its metaphysical
nature; yet others, supported by facts which incontrovertibly prove
the entire dependence of the intellect upon the bodily organism,
unweariedly maintain the contrary. That soul is by all and before
everything taken asabsolutely simple; for precisely from this its metaphysical nature, its
immateriality and immortality [pg 003] were proved, although these
by no means necessarily follow from it. For although we can only
conceive the destruction of a formed body through breaking up of it
into its parts, it does not follow from this that the destruction
of a simple existence, of which besides we have no conception, may
not be possible in some other way, perhaps by gradually vanishing.
I, on the contrary, start by doing away with the presupposed
simplicity of our subjectively conscious nature, or theego, inasmuch as I show that the
manifestations from which it was deduced have two very different
sources, and that in any case the intellect is physically
conditioned, the function of a material organ, therefore dependent
upon it, and without it is just as impossible as the grasp without
the hand; that accordingly it belongs to the mere phenomenon, and
thus shares the fate of this,—that thewill, on the contrary, is bound to no
special organ, but is everywhere present, is everywhere that which
moves and forms, and therefore is that which conditions the whole
organism; that, in fact, it constitutes the metaphysical substratum
of the whole phenomenon, consequently is not, like the intellect,
aPosteriusof it, but
itsPrius; and the phenomenon
depends upon it, not it upon the phenomenon. But the body is
reduced indeed to a mere idea, for it is only the manner in which
thewillexhibits itself in the
perception of the intellect or brain. Thewill, again, which in all other
systems, different as they are in other respects, appears as one of
the last results, is with me the very first. Theintellect, as mere function of the
brain, is involved in the destruction of the body, but thewillis by no means so. From this
heterogeneity of the two, together with the subordinate nature of
the intellect, it becomes conceivable that man, in the depths of
his self-consciousness, feels himself to be eternal and
indestructible, but yet can have no memory, eithera parte anteora
parte post, beyond the duration of his life. I
do not wish to anticipate here the exposition of the true
indestructibility of our nature, which has its place in the [pg
004] fourth book, but have only sought to indicate the place where
it links itself on.But now that, in an expression which is certainly one-sided,
yet from our standpoint true, the body is called a mere idea
depends upon the fact than an existence in space, as something
extended, and in time, as something that changes, and more closely
determined in both through the causal-nexus, is only possible in
theidea, for all those
determinations rest upon its forms, thus in a brain, in which
accordingly such an existence appears as something
objective,i.e., foreign;
therefore even our own body can have this kind of existence only in
a brain. For the knowledge which I have of my body as extended,
space-occupying, and movable, is onlyindirect: it is a picture in my brain
which is brought about by means of the senses and understanding.
The body is given to medirectlyonly in muscular action and in pain and pleasure, both of
which primarily and directly belong to thewill. But the combination of these two
different kinds of knowledge of my own body afterwards affords the
further insight that all other things which also have the objective
existence described, which is primarily only in my brain, are not
therefore entirely non-existent apart from it, but must also
ultimatelyin themselvesbe that
which makes itself known in self-consciousness aswill.Chapter XXII.1Objective View of the
Intellect.There are two fundamentally different ways of regarding the
intellect, which depend upon the difference of the point of view,
and, much as they are opposed to each other in consequence of this,
must yet be brought into agreement. One is thesubjective, which, starting
fromwithinand taking
theconsciousnessas the given,
shows us by what mechanism the world exhibits itself in it, and
how, out of the materials which the senses and the understanding
provide, it constructs itself in it. We must look upon Locke as the
originator of this method of consideration; Kant brought it to
incomparably higher perfection; and our first book also, together
with its supplements, are devoted to it.The method of considering the intellect which is opposed to
this is theobjective, which
starts fromwithout, takes as
its object not our own consciousness, but the beings given in
outward experience, conscious of themselves and of the world, and
now investigates the relation of their intellect to their other
qualities, how it has become possible, how it has become necessary,
and what it accomplishes for them. The standpoint of this method of
consideration is the empirical. It takes the world and the animal
existences present in it as absolutely given, in that it starts
from them. It is accordingly primarily zoological, anatomical,
physiological, and only becomes philosophical by connection with
that first method of consideration, and [pg 006] from the higher
point of view thereby attained. The only foundations of this which
as yet have been given we owe to zootomists and physiologists, for
the most part French. Here Cabanis is specially to be named, whose
excellent work, “Des rapports du physique au
moral,” is initiatory of this method of
consideration on the path of physiology. The famous Bichat was his
contemporary, but his theme was a much more comprehensive one. Even
Gall may be named here, although his chief aim was missed.
Ignorance and prejudice have raised against this method of
consideration the accusation of materialism, because, adhering
simply to experience, it does not know the immaterial substance,
soul. The most recent advances in the physiology of the nervous
system, through Sir Charles Bell, Magendie, Marshall Hall, and
others, have also enriched and corrected the material of this
method of consideration. A philosophy which, like the Kantian,
entirely ignores this point of view for the intellect is one-sided,
and consequently inadequate. It leaves an impassable gulf between
our philosophical and our physiological knowledge, with which we
can never find satisfaction.Although what I have said in the two preceding chapters
concerning the life and the activity of the brain belongs to this
method of consideration, and in the same way all the discussions to
be found under the heading, “Pflanzenphysiologie,” in the essay,
“Ueber den Willen in der Natur,” and also a portion of those under the heading “Vergleichende Anatomie,” are devoted
to it, the following exposition of its results in general will be
by no means superfluous.We become most vividly conscious of the glaring contrast
between the two methods of considering the intellect opposed to
each other above if we carry the matter to the extreme and realise
that what the one, as reflective thought and vivid perception,
directly assumes and makes its material is for the other nothing
more than the physiological [pg 007] function of an internal organ,
the brain; nay, that we are justified in asserting that the whole
objective world, so boundless in space, so infinite in time, so
unsearchable in its perfection, is really only a certain movement
or affection of the pulpy matter in the skull. We then ask in
astonishment: what is this brain whose function produces such a
phenomenon of all phenomena? What is the matter which can be
refined and potentiated to such a pulp that the stimulation of a
few of its particles becomes the conditional supporter of the
existence of an objective world? The fear of such questions led to
the hypothesis of the simple substance of an immaterial soul, which
merely dwelt in the brain. We say boldly: this pulp also, like
every vegetable or animal part, is an organic structure, like all
its poorer relations in the inferior accommodation of the heads of
our irrational brethren, down to the lowest, which scarcely
apprehends at all; yet that organic pulp is the last product of
nature, which presupposes all the rest. But in itself, and outside
the idea, the brain also, like everything else, iswill.For existing
for another is being perceived; being in itself is
willing: upon this it depends that on the purely
objective path we never attain to the inner nature of things; but
if we attempt to find their inner nature from without and
empirically, this inner always becomes an outer again in our
hands,—the pith of the tree, as well as its bark; the heart of the
animal, as well as its hide; the white and the yolk of an egg, as
well as its shell. On the other hand, upon the subjective path the
inner is accessible to us at every moment; for we find it as
thewillprimarily in ourselves,
and must, by the clue of the analogy with our own nature, be able
to solve that of others, in that we attain to the insight that a
being in itself independent of being known,i.e., of exhibiting itself in an
intellect, is only conceivable as willing.If now, in theobjectivecomprehension of the intellect, we go back as far as we
possibly can, we shall find that [pg 008] the necessity or the need
ofknowledge in generalarises
from the multiplicity and theseparateexistence of beings, thus from individuation. For suppose
there only existeda singlebeing, such a being would have no need of knowledge: because
nothing would exist which was different from it, and whose
existence it would therefore have to take up into itself indirectly
through knowledge,i.e., image
and concept. It woulditselfalready be all in all, and therefore there would remain
nothing for it to know,i.e.,
nothing foreign that could be apprehended as object. In the case of
a multiplicity of beings, on the other hand, every individual finds
itself in a condition of isolation from all the rest, and hence
arises the necessity of knowledge. The nervous system, by means of
which the animal individual primarily becomes conscious of itself,
is bounded by a skin; yet in the brain that has attained to
intellect it passes beyond this limit by means of its form of
knowledge, causality, and thus there arises for it perception as a
consciousness ofotherthings,
as an image of beings in space and time, which change in accordance
with causality. In this sense it would be more correct to say,
“Only the different is known by the different,” than as Empedocles
said, “Only the like is known by the like,” which was a very
indefinite and ambiguous proposition; although points of view may
certainly also be conceived from which it is true; as, for
instance, we may observe in passing that of Helvetius when he says
so beautifully and happily: “Il n'y a que
l'esprit qui sente l'esprit: c'est une corde qui ne frémit qu'à
l'unison,” which corresponds with Xenophon's
“σοφον ειναι δει τον επιγνωσομενον τον σοφον” (sapientem esse opportet eum, qui sapientem agniturus
sit), and is a great sorrow. But now, again,
from the other side we know that multiplicity of similars only
becomes possible through time and space; thus through the forms of
our knowledge. Space first arises in that the knowing subject sees
externally; it is the manner in which the subject comprehends
something as [pg 009] different from itself. But we also saw
knowledge in general conditioned by multiplicity and difference.
Thus knowledge and multiplicity, or individuation, stand and fall
together, for they reciprocally condition each other. Hence it must
be inferred that, beyond the phenomenon in the true being of all
things, to which time and space, and consequently also
multiplicity, must be foreign, there can also be no knowledge.
Buddhism defines this asPratschna
Paramita,i.e., that which is beyond all knowledge (J. J. Schmidt, “On the
Maha-Jana and Pratschna Paramita”). A “knowledge of things in
themselves,” in the strictest sense of the word, would accordingly
be already impossible from the fact that where the thing in itself
begins knowledge ceases, and all knowledge is essentially concerned
only with phenomena. For it springs from a limitation, by which it
is made necessary, in order to extend the limits.For the objective consideration the brain is the
efflorescence of the organism; therefore only where the latter has
attained its highest perfection and complexity does the brain
appear in its greatest development. But in the preceding chapter we
have recognised the organism as the objectification of the will;
therefore the brain also, as a part of it, must belong to this
objectification. Further, from the fact that the organism is only
the visibility of the will, thus in itself is the will, I have
deduced that every affection of the organism at once and directly
affects the will,i.e., is felt
as agreeable or painful. Yet, with the heightening of sensibility,
in the higher development of the nervous system, the possibility
arises that in the nobler,i.e., theobjective, organs
of sense (sight and hearing) the exquisitely delicate affections
proper to them are perceived without in themselves and directly
affecting the will, that is, without being either painful or
agreeable, and that therefore they appear in consciousness as
indifferent, merely perceived, sensations. But in the brain this
heightening of sensibility reaches such a high degree that upon [pg
010] received impressions of sense a reaction even takes place,
which does not proceed directly from the will, but is primarily a
spontaneity of the function of understanding, which makes the
transition from the directly perceived sensation of the senses to
itscause; and since the brain
then at once produces the form of space, there thus arises the
perception of anexternal object. We may therefore regard the point at which the
understanding makes the transition from the mere sensation upon the
retina, which is still a mere affection of the body and therefore
of the will, to thecauseof
that sensation, which it projects by means of its form of space, as
something external and different from its own body, as the boundary
between the world as will and the world as idea, or as the
birthplace of the latter. In man, however, the spontaneity of the
activity of the brain, which in the last instance is certainly
conferred by the will, goes further than mereperceptionand immediate comprehension
of causal relations. It extends to the construction of abstract
conceptions out of these perceptions, and to operating with these
conceptions,i.e., tothinking, as that in which hisreasonconsists.Thoughtsare therefore furthest removed
from the affections of the body, which, since the body is the
objectification of the will, may, through increased intensity, pass
at once into pain, even in the organs of sense. Accordingly idea
and thought may also be regarded as the efflorescence of the will,
because they spring from the highest perfection and development of
the organism; but the organism, in itself and apart from the idea,
is thewill. Of course, in my
explanation, the existence of the body presupposes the world of
idea; inasmuch as it also, as body or real object, is only in this
world; and, on the other hand, the idea itself just as much
presupposes the body, for it arises only through the function of an
organ of the body. That which lies at the foundation of the whole
phenomenon, that in it which alone has being in itself and is
original, is exclusively thewill; for it is the [pg 011] will which through this very process
assumes the form of theidea,i.e., enters the
secondary existence of an objective world, or the sphere of the
knowable. Philosophers before Kant, with few exceptions, approached
the explanation of the origin of our knowledge from the wrong side.
They set out from a so-called soul, an existence whose inner nature
and peculiar function consisted in thinking, and indeed quite
specially in abstract thinking, with mere conceptions, which
belonged to it the more completely the further they lay from all
perception. (I beg to refer here to the note at the end of § 6 of
my prize essay on the foundation of morals.) This soul has in some
inconceivable manner entered the body, and there it is only
disturbed in its pure thinking, first by impressions of the senses
and perceptions, still more by the desires which these excite, and
finally by the emotions, nay, passions, to which these desires
develop; while the characteristic and original element of this soul
is mere abstract thinking, and given up to this it has only
universals, inborn conceptions, andæternæ
veritatesfor its objects, and leaves everything
perceptible lying far below it. Hence, also, arises the contempt
with which even now “sensibility” and the "sensuous" are referred
to by professors of philosophy, nay, are even made the chief source
of immorality, while it is just the senses which are the genuine
and innocent source of all our knowledge, from which all thinking
must first borrow its material, for in combination with thea priorifunctions of the intellect
they produce theperception.
One might really suppose that in speaking of sensibility these
gentlemen always think only of the pretended sixth sense of the
French. Thus, as we have said, in the process of knowledge, its
ultimate product was made that which is first and original in it,
and accordingly the matter was taken hold of by the wrong end.
According to my exposition, the intellect springs from the
organism, and thereby from the will, and hence could not be without
the latter. Thus, without the will it would also [pg 012] find no
material to occupy it; for everything that is knowable is just the
objectification of the will.But not only the perception of the external world, or the
consciousness of other things, is conditioned by the brain and its
functions, but also self-consciousness. The will in itself is
without consciousness, and remains so in the greater part of its
phenomena. The secondary world of idea must be added, in order that
it may become conscious of itself, just as light only becomes
visible through the bodies which reflect it, and without them loses
itself in darkness without producing any effect. Because the will,
with the aim of comprehending its relations to the external world,
produces a brain in the animal individual, the consciousness of its
own self arises in it, by means of the subject of knowledge, which
comprehends things as existing and theegoas willing. The sensibility, which
reaches its highest degree in the brain, but is yet dispersed
through its different parts, must first of all collect all the rays
of its activity, concentrate them, as it were, in a focus, which,
however, does not lie without, as in the case of the concave
mirror, but within, as in the convex mirror. With this point now it
first describes the line of time, upon which, therefore, all that
it presents to itself as idea must exhibit itself, and which is the
first and most essential form of all knowledge, or the form of
inner sense. This focus of the whole activity of the brain is what
Kant called the synthetic unity of apperception (cf.vol. ii. p. 475). Only by means of
this does the will become conscious of itself, because this focus
of the activity of the brain, or that which knows, apprehends
itself as identical with its own basis, from which it springs, that
which wills; and thus theegoarises. Yet this focus of the brain activity remains
primarily a mere subject of knowledge, and as such capable of being
the cold and impartial spectator, the mere guide and counsellor of
the will, and also of comprehending the external world in a purely
objective manner, [pg 013] without reference to the will and its
weal or woe. But whenever it turns within, it recognises the will
as the basis of its own phenomenon, and therefore combines with it
in the consciousness of anego.
That focus of the activity of the brain (or the subject of
knowledge) is indeed, as an indivisible point, simple, but yet is
not on this account a substance (soul), but a mere condition or
state. That of which it is itself a condition or state can only be
known by it indirectly, as it were through reflection. But the
ceasing of this state must not be regarded as the annihilation of
that of which it is a state. Thisknowingand consciousegois related to the will, which is
the basis of its phenomenal appearance, as the picture in the focus
of a concave mirror is related to the mirror itself, and has, like
that picture, only a conditioned, nay, really a merely apparent,
reality. Far from being the absolutely first (as, for example,
Fichte teaches), it is at bottom tertiary, for it presupposes the
organism, and the organism presupposes the will. I admit that all
that is said here is really only an image and a figure, and in part
also hypothetical; but we stand at a point to which thought can
scarcely reach, not to speak of proof. I therefore request the
reader to compare with this what I have adduced at length on this
subject in chapter 20.Now, although the true being of everything that exists
consists in its will, and knowledge together with consciousness are
only added at the higher grades of the phenomenon as something
secondary, yet we find that the difference which the presence and
the different degree of consciousness places between one being and
another is exceedingly great and of important results. The
subjective existence of the plant we must think of as a weak
analogue, a mere shadow of comfort and discomfort; and even in this
exceedingly weak degree the plant knows only of itself, not of
anything outside of it. On the other hand, even the lowest animal
standing next to it is forced by increased and more definitely
specified wants to extend [pg 014] the sphere of its existence
beyond the limits of its own body. This takes place through
knowledge. It has a dim apprehension of its immediate surroundings,
out of which the motives for its action with a view to its own
maintenance arise. Thus accordingly themedium of
motivesappears, and this is—the world existing
objectively in time and space,the world as
idea, however weak, obscure, and dimly dawning
this first and lowest example of it may be. But it imprints itself
ever more and more distinctly, ever wider and deeper, in proportion
as in the ascending scale of animal organisations the brain is ever
more perfectly produced. This progress in the development of the
brain, thus of the intellect, and of the clearness of the idea, at
each of these ever higher grades is, however, brought about by the
constantly increasing and more complicatedwantsof this phenomenon of the will.
This must always first afford the occasion for it, for without
necessity nature (i.e., the
will which objectifies itself in it) produces nothing, least of all
the hardest of its productions—a more perfect brain: in consequence
of itslex parsimoniæ:natura nihil agit frustra et nihil facit
supervacaneum. It has provided every animal with
the organs which are necessary for its sustenance and the weapons
necessary for its conflict, as I have shown at length in my work,
“Ueber den Willen in der Natur,” under the heading, “Vergleichende
Anatomie.” According to this measure, therefore,
it imparts to each the most important of those organs concerned
with what is without, the brain, with its function the intellect.
The more complicated, through higher development, its organisation
became, the more multifarious and specially determined did its
wants also become, and consequently the more difficult and the more
dependent upon opportunity was the provision of what would satisfy
them. Thus there was needed here a wider range of sight, a more
accurate comprehension, a more correct distinction of things in the
external world, in all their circumstances and relations.
Accordingly we see the faculty of forming ideas, and its [pg 015]
organs, brain, nerves, and special senses, appear ever more perfect
the higher we advance in the scale of animals; and in proportion as
the cerebral system develops, the external world appears ever more
distinct, many-sided, and complete in consciousness. The
comprehension of it now demands ever more attention, and ultimately
in such a degree that sometimes its relation to the will must
momentarily be lost sight of in order that it may take place more
purely and correctly. Quite definitely this first appears in the
case of man. With him alone does apure separation
of knowing and willingtake place. This is an
important point, which I merely touch on here in order to indicate
its position, and be able to take it up again later. But, like all
the rest, nature takes this last step also in extending and
perfecting the brain, and thereby in increasing the powers of
knowledge, only in consequence of the increased needs, thus in the
service of thewill. What this
aims at and attains in man is indeed essentially the same, and not
more than what is also its goal in the brutes—nourishment and
propagation. But the requisites for the attainment of this goal
became so much increased in number, and of so much higher quality
and greater definiteness through the organisation of man, that a
very much more considerable heightening of the intellect than the
previous steps demanded was necessary, or at least was the easiest
means of reaching the end. But since now the intellect, in
accordance with its nature, is a tool of the most various utility,
and is equally applicable to the most different kinds of ends,
nature, true to her spirit of parsimony, could now meet through it
alone all the demands of the wants which had now become so
manifold. Therefore she sent forth man without clothing, without
natural means of protection or weapons of attack, nay, with
relatively little muscular power, combined with great frailty and
little endurance of adverse influences and wants, in reliance upon
that one great tool, in addition to which she had only to retain
the hands from the next grade below him, the ape. [pg 016] But
through the predominating intellect which here appears not only is
the comprehension of motives, their multiplicity, and in general
the horizon of the aims infinitely increased, but also the
distinctness with which the will is consciousof
itselfis enhanced in the highest degree in
consequence of the clearness of the whole consciousness which has
been brought about, which is supported by the capacity for abstract
knowledge, and now attains to complete reflectiveness. But thereby,
and also through the vehemence of the will, which is necessarily
presupposed as the supporter of such a heightened intellect, an
intensifying of all theemotionsappears, and indeed the possibility of thepassions, which, properly speaking,
are unknown to the brute. For the vehemence of the will keeps pace
with the advance of intelligence, because this advance really
always springs from the increased needs and pressing demands of the
will: besides this, however, the two reciprocally support each
other. Thus the vehemence of the character corresponds to the
greater energy of the beating of the heart and the circulation of
the blood, which physically heighten the activity of the brain. On
the other hand, the clearness of the intelligence intensifies the
emotions, which are called forth by the outward circumstances, by
means of the more vivid apprehension of the latter. Hence, for
example, young calves quietly allow themselves to be packed in a
cart and carried off; but young lions, if they are only separated
from their mother, remain permanently restless, and roar
unceasingly from morning to night; children in such a position
would cry and vex themselves almost to death. The vivaciousness and
impetuosity of the ape is in exact proportion to its greatly
developed intellect. It depends just on this reciprocal
relationship that man is, in general, capable of far greater
sorrows than the brute, but also of greater joy in satisfied and
pleasing emotions. In the same way his higher intelligence makes
him more sensible toennuithan
the brute; but it also becomes, if he is individually very [pg 017]
complete, an inexhaustible source of entertainment. Thus, as a
whole, the manifestation of the will in man is related to that in
the brute of the higher species, as a note that has been struck to
its fifth pitched two or three octaves lower. But between the
different kinds of brutes also the differences of intellect, and
thereby of consciousness, are great and endlessly graduated. The
mere analogy of consciousness which we must yet attribute to plants
will be related to the still far deader subjective nature of an
unorganised body, very much as the consciousness of the lowest
species of animals is related to thequasiconsciousness of plants. We may
present to our imagination the innumerable gradations in the degree
of consciousness under the figure of the different velocity of
points which are unequally distant from the centre of a revolving
sphere. But the most correct, and indeed, as our third book
teaches, the natural figure of that gradation is afforded us by the
scale in its whole compass from the lowest audible note to the
highest. It is, however, the grade of consciousness which
determines the grade of existence of a being. For every immediate
existence is subjective: the objective existence is in the
consciousness of another, thus only for this other, consequently
quite indirect. Through the grade of consciousness beings are as
different as through the will they are alike, for the will is what
is common to them all.But what we have now considered between the plant and the
animal, and then between the different species of animals, occurs
also between man and man. Here also that which is secondary, the
intellect, by means of the clearness of consciousness and
distinctness of knowledge which depends upon it, constitutes a
fundamental and immeasurably great difference in the whole manner
of the existence, and thereby in the grade of it. The higher the
consciousness has risen, the more distinct and connected are the
thoughts, the clearer the perceptions the more intense the
sensations. Through it everything gains [pg 018] more depth:
emotion, sadness, joy, and sorrow. Commonplace blockheads are not
even capable of real joy: they live on in dull insensibility. While
to one man his consciousness only presents his own existence,
together with the motives which must be apprehended for the purpose
of sustaining and enlivening it, in a bare comprehension of the
external world, it is to another acamera
obscurain which the macrocosm exhibits
itself:
“He feels that he holds a little worldBrooding in his brain,That it begins to work and to live,That he fain would give it forth.”The difference of the whole manner of existence which the
extremes of the gradation of intellectual capacity establish
between man and man is so great that that between a king and a day
labourer seems small in comparison. And here also, as in the case
of the species of animals, a connection between the vehemence of
the will and the height of the intellect can be shown. Genius is
conditioned by a passionate temperament, and a phlegmatic genius is
inconceivable: it seems as if an exceptionally vehement, thus a
violently longing, will must be present if nature is to give an
abnormally heightened intellect, as corresponding to it; while the
merely physical account of this points to the greater energy with
which the arteries of the head move the brain and increase its
turgescence. Certainly, however, the quantity, quality, and form of
the brain itself is the other and incomparably more rare condition
of genius. On the other hand, phlegmatic persons are as a rule of
very moderate mental power; and thus the northern, cold-blooded,
and phlegmatic nations are in general noticeably inferior in mind
to the southern vivacious and passionate peoples; although, as
Bacon2has most pertinently
remarked, if once a man of a northern nation is highly gifted by
nature, he can then reach a grade which no southern ever attains
to. It is accordingly as perverse [pg 019] as it is common to take
the great minds of different nations as the standard for comparing
their mental powers: for that is just attempting to prove the rule
by the exceptions. It is rather the great majority of each nation
that one has to consider: for one swallow does not make a summer.
We have further to remark here that that very passionateness which
is a condition of genius, bound up with its vivid apprehension of
things, produces in practical life, where the will comes into play,
and especially in the case of sudden occurrences, so great an
excitement of the emotions that it disturbs and confuses the
intellect; while the phlegmatic man in such a case still retains
the full use of his mental faculties, though they are much more
limited, and then accomplishes much more with them than the
greatest genius can achieve. Accordingly a passionate temperament
is favourable to the original quality of the intellect, but a
phlegmatic temperament to its use. Therefore genius proper is only
for theoretical achievements, for which it can choose and await its
time, which will just be the time at which the will is entirely at
rest, and no waves disturb the clear mirror of the comprehension of
the world. On the other hand, genius is ill adapted and
unserviceable for practical life, and is therefore for the most
part unfortunate. Goethe's “Tasso” is written from this point of
view. As now genius proper depends upon theabsolutestrength of the intellect,
which must be purchased by a correspondingly excessive vehemence of
disposition, so, on the other hand, the great pre-eminence in
practical life that makes generals and statesmen depends upon
therelativestrength of the
intellect, thus upon the highest degree of it that can be attained
without too great excitability of the emotions, and too great
vehemence of character, and that therefore can hold its own even in
the storm. Great firmness of will and constancy of mind, together
with a capable and fine understanding, are here sufficient; and
whatever goes beyond this acts detrimentally, for too great a
development of [pg 020] the intelligence directly impedes firmness
of character and resolution of will. Hence this kind of eminence is
not so abnormal, and is a hundred times less rare than the former
kind; and accordingly we see great generals and great ministers
appear in every age, whenever the merely external conditions are
favourable to their efficiency. Great poets and philosophers, on
the other hand, leave centuries waiting for them; and yet humanity
may be contented even with this rare appearance of them, for their
works remain, and do not exist only for the present, like the
achievements of those other men. It is also quite in keeping with
the law of the parsimony of nature referred to above that it
bestows great eminence of mind in general upon very few, and genius
only as the rarest of all exceptions, while it equips the great
mass of the human race with no more mental power than is required
for the maintenance of the individual and the species. For the
great, and through their very satisfaction, constantly increasing
needs of the human race make it necessary that the great majority
of men should pass their lives in occupations of a coarsely
physical and entirely mechanical description. And what would be the
use to them of an active mind, a glowing imagination, a subtle
understanding, and a profoundly penetrating intellect? These would
only make them useless and unhappy. Therefore nature has thus gone
about the most costly of all her productions in the least
extravagant manner. In order not to judge unfairly one ought also
to settle definitely one's expectations of the mental achievements
of men generally from this point of view, and to regard, for
example, even learned men, since as a rule they have become so only
by the force of outward circumstances, primarily as men whom nature
really intended to be tillers of the soil; indeed even professors
of philosophy ought to be estimated according to this standard, and
then their achievements will be found to come up to all fair
expectations. It is worth noticing that in the south, where the
necessities of life press less [pg 021] severely upon the human
race, and more leisure is allowed, the mental faculties even of the
multitude also become more active and finer. It is physiologically
noteworthy that the preponderance of the mass of the brain over
that of the spinal cord and the nerves, which, according to
Sömmerring's acute discovery, affords the true and closest measure
of the degree of intelligence both of species of brutes and of
individual men, at the same time increases the direct power of
moving, the agility of the limbs; because, through the great
inequality of the relation, the dependence of all motor nerves upon
the brain becomes more decided; and besides this the cerebellum,
which is the primary controller of movements, shares the
qualitative perfection of the cerebrum; thus through both all
voluntary movements gain greater facility, rapidity, and
manageableness, and by the concentration of the starting-point of
all activity that arises which Lichtenberg praises in Garrick:
“that he appeared to be present in all the muscles of his body.”
Hence clumsiness in the movement of the body indicates clumsiness
in the movement of the thoughts, and will be regarded as a sign of
stupidity both in individuals and nations, as much as sleepiness of
the countenance and vacancy of the glance. Another symptom of the
physiological state of the case referred to is the fact that many
persons are obliged at once to stand still whenever their
conversation with any one who is walking with them begins to gain
some connection; because their brain, as soon as it has to link
together a few thoughts, has no longer as much power over as is
required to keep the limbs in motion by means of the motory nerves,
so closely is everything measured with them.It results from this whole objective consideration of the
intellect and its origin, that it is designed for the comprehension
of those ends upon the attainment of which depends the individual
life and its propagation, but by no means for deciphering the inner
nature of things and of the world, which exists independently of
the knower. [pg 022] What to the plant is the susceptibility to
light, in consequence of which it guides its growth in the
direction of it, that is, in kind, the knowledge of the brute, nay,
even of man, although in degree it is increased in proportion as
the needs of each of these beings demand. With them all
apprehension remains a mere consciousness of their relations to
other things, and is by no means intended to present again in the
consciousness of the knower the peculiar, absolutely real nature of
these things. Rather, as springing from the will, the intellect is
also only designed for its service, thus for the apprehension of
motives; it is adapted for this, and is therefore of a thoroughly
practical tendency. This also holds good if we conceive the
significance of life as ethical; for in this regard too we find man
knowing only for the benefit of his conduct. Such a faculty of
knowledge, existing exclusively for practical ends, will from its
nature always comprehend only the relations of things to each
other, but not the inner nature of them, as it is in itself. But to
regard the complex of these relations as the absolute nature of the
world as it is in itself, and the manner in which it necessarily
exhibits itself in accordance with the laws predisposed in the
brain as the eternal laws of the existence of all things, and then
to construct ontology, cosmology, and theology in accordance with
this view—this was really the old fundamental error, of which
Kant's teaching has made an end. Here, then, our objective, and
therefore for the most part physiological consideration of the
intellect meetshistranscendental consideration of it; nay, appears in a certain
sense even as ana prioriinsight into it; for, from a point of view which we have
taken up outside of it, our objective view enables us to know in
its origin, and therefore asnecessary, what that transcendental consideration, starting from facts
of consciousness, presents only as a matter of fact. For it follows
from our objective consideration of the intellect, that the world
as idea, as it exists stretched out in space and time, and moves on
[pg 023] regularly according to the strict law of causality, is
primarily only a physiological phenomenon, a function of the brain,
which brings it about, certainly upon the occasion of certain
external stimuli, but yet in conformity with its own laws.
Accordingly it is beforehand a matter of course, that what goes on
in this function itself, and therefore through it and for it, must
by no means be regarded as the nature ofthings in
themselves, which exist independently of it and
are entirely different from it, but primarily exhibits only the
mode or manner of this function itself, which can always receive
only a very subordinate modification through that which exists
completely independently of it, and sets it in motion as a
stimulus. As, then, Locke claimed for the organs of sense all that
comes into our apprehension by means of the sensation, in order to
deny that it belongs to things in themselves, so Kant, with the
same intention, and pursuing the same path further, has proved all
that makesperceptionproper
possible, thus space, time, and causality, to be functions of the
brain; although he has refrained from using this physiological
expression, to which, however, our present method of investigation,
coming from the opposite side, the side of the real, necessarily
leads us. Kant arrived upon his analytical path at the result that
what we know are merephenomena. What this mysterious expression really means becomes clear
from our objective and genetic investigation of the intellect. The
phenomena are the motives for the aims of individual will as they
exhibit themselves in the intellect which the will has produced for
this purpose (which itself appears as a phenomenon objectively, as
the brain), and which, when comprehended, as far as one can follow
their concatenation, afford us in their connection the world which
extends itself objectively in time and space, and which I call the
world as idea. Moreover, from our point of view, the objectionable
element vanishes which in the Kantian doctrine arises from the fact
that, because the intellect [pg 024] knows merely phenomena instead
of things as they are in themselves, nay, in consequence of this is
led astray into paralogisms and unfounded hypostases by means of
“sophistications, not of men but of the reason itself, from which
even the wisest does not free himself, and if, perhaps indeed after
much trouble, he avoids error, can yet never get quit of the
illusion which unceasingly torments and mocks him”—because of all
this, I say, the appearance arises that our intellect is
intentionally designed to lead us into errors. For the objective
view of the intellect given here, which contains a genesis of it,
makes it conceivable that, being exclusively intended for practical
ends, it is merely themedium of
motives, and therefore fulfils its end by an
accurate presentation of these, and that if we undertake to
discover the nature of things in themselves, from the manifold
phenomena which here exhibit themselves objectively to us, and
their laws, we do this at our own peril and on our own
responsibility. We have recognised that the original inner force of
nature, without knowledge and working in the dark, which, if it has
worked its way up to self-consciousness, reveals itself to this
aswill, attains to this grade
only by the production of an animal brain and of knowledge, as its
function, whereupon the phenomenon of the world of perception
arises in this brain. But to explain this mere brain phenomenon,
with the conformity to law which is invariably connected with its
functions, as the objective inner nature of the world and the
things in it, which is independent of the brain, existing before
and after it, is clearly a spring which nothing warrants us in
making. From thismundus phœnomenon, however, from this perception which arises under such a
variety of conditions, all our conceptions are drawn. They have all
their content from it, or even only in relation to it. Therefore,
as Kant says, they are only for immanent, not for transcendental,
use; that is to say, these conceptions of ours, this first material
of thought, and consequently [pg 025] still more the judgments
which result from their combination, are unfitted for the task of
thinking the nature of things in themselves, and the true
connection of the world and existence; indeed, to undertake this is
analogous to expressing the stereometrical content of a body in
square inches. For our intellect, originally only intended to
present to an individual will its paltry aims, comprehends
accordingly mererelationsof
things, and does not penetrate to their inner being, to their real
nature. It is therefore a merely superficial force, clings to the
surface of things, and apprehends merespecies
transitivas, not the true being of things. From
this it arises that we cannot understand and comprehend any single
thing, even the simplest and smallest, through and through, but
something remains entirely inexplicable to us in each of them. Just
because the intellect is a product of nature, and is therefore only
intended for its ends, the Christian mystics have very aptly called
it “the light of nature,” and driven it back within its limits; for
nature is the object to which alone it is the subject. The thought
from which the Critique of Pure Reason has sprung really lies
already at the foundation of this expression. That we cannot
comprehend the world on the direct path,i.e., through the uncritical, direct
application of the intellect and its data, but when we reflect upon
it become ever more deeply involved in insoluble mysteries, points
to the fact that the intellect, thus knowledge itself, is
secondary, a mere product, brought about by the development of the
inner being of the world, which consequently till then preceded it,
and it at last appeared as a breaking through to the light out of
the obscure depths of the unconscious striving the nature of which
exhibits itself aswillto the
self-consciousness which now at once arises. That which preceded
knowledge as its condition, whereby it first became possible, thus
its own basis, cannot be directly comprehended by it; as the eye
cannot see itself. It is rather the relations of one existence to
another, exhibiting themselves [pg 026] upon the surface of things,
which alone are its affair, and are so only by means of the
apparatus of the intellect, its forms, space, time, and causality.
Just because the world has made itself without the assistance of
knowledge, its whole being does not enter into knowledge, but
knowledge presupposes the existence of the world; on which account
the origin of the world does not lie within its sphere. It is
accordingly limited to the relations between the things which lie
before it, and is thus sufficient for the individual will, for the
service of which alone it appeared. For the intellect is, as has
been shown, conditioned by nature, lies in it, belongs to it, and
cannot therefore place itself over against it as something quite
foreign to it, in order thus to take up into itself its whole
nature, absolutely, objectively, and thoroughly. It can, if fortune
favours it, understand all that is in nature, but not nature
itself, at least not directly.However discouraging to metaphysics this essential limitation
of the intellect may be, which arises from its nature and origin,
it has yet another side which is very consoling. It deprives the
direct utterances of nature of their unconditional validity, in the
assertion of whichnaturalismproper consists. If, therefore, nature presents to us every
living thing as appearing out of nothing, and, after an ephemeral
existence, returning again for ever to nothing, and if it seems to
take pleasure in the unceasing production of new beings, in order
that it may be able unceasingly to destroy, and, on the other hand,
is unable to bring anything permanent to light; if accordingly we
are forced to recognisematteras that which alone is permanent, which never came into being
and never passes away, but brings forth all things from its womb,
whence its name appears to be derived frommater
rerum, and along with it, as the father of
things,form, which, just as
fleeting as matter is permanent, changes really every moment, and
can only maintain itself so long as it clings as a parasite to
matter (now to one part of it, now to [pg 027] another), but when
once it entirely loses hold, disappears, as is shown by the
palæotheria and the ichthyosaurians, we must indeed recognise this
as the direct and genuine utterance of nature, but on account of
the origin of the intellect explained above, and the nature of it
which results from this origin, we cannot ascribe to this utterance
anunconditional truth, but
rather only an entirelyconditionaltruth, which Kant has appropriately indicated as such by
calling it thephenomenonin
opposition to thething in itself.If, in spite of this essential limitation of the intellect,
it is possible, by a circuitous route, to arrive at a certain
understanding of the world and the nature of things, by means of
reflection widely pursued, and the skilful combination of objective
knowledge directed towards without, with the data of
self-consciousness, this will yet be only a very limited, entirely
indirect, and relative understanding, a parabolical translation
into the forms of knowledge, thus aquadam prodire
tenus, which must always leave many problems
still unsolved. On the other hand, the fundamental error of the
olddogmatismin all its forms,
which was destroyed by Kant, was this, that it started absolutely
fromknowledge, i.e.,the world as idea, in order to deduce
and construct from its laws being in general, whereby it accepted
that world of idea, together with its laws, as absolutely existing
and absolutely real; while its whole existence is throughout
relative, and a mere result or phenomenon of the true being which
lies at its foundation,—or, in other words, that it constructed an
ontology when it had only materials for a dianoiology. Kant
discovered the subjectively conditioned and therefore entirely
immanent nature of knowledge,i.e., its unsuitableness for transcendental use, from the
constitution of knowledge itself; and therefore he very
appropriately called his doctrine theCritique of
Reason. He accomplished this partly by showing
the important and thoroughlya prioripart of all knowledge, which, as throughout subjective, [pg
028] spoils all objectivity, and partly by professedly proving that
if they were followed out to the end the principles of knowledge,
taken as purely objective, led to contradictions. He had, however,
hastily assumed that, apart fromobjectiveknowledge,i.e., apart from the world asidea, there is nothing given us except
conscience, out of which he constructed the little that still
remained of metaphysics, his moral theology, to which, however, he
attributed absolutely only a practical validity, and no theoretical
validity at all. He had overlooked that although certainly
objective knowledge, or the world as idea, affords nothing but
phenomena, together with their phenomenal connection and regressus,
yet our own nature necessarily also belongs to the world of things
in themselves, for it must have its root in it. But here, even if
the root itself cannot be brought to light, it must be possible to
gather some data for the explanation of the connection of the world
of phenomena with the inner nature of things. Thus here lies the
path upon which I have gone beyond Kant and the limits which he
drew, yet always restricting myself to the ground of reflection,
and consequently of honesty, and therefore without the vain
pretension of intellectual intuition or absolute thought which
characterises the period of pseudo-philosophy between Kant and me.
In his proof of the insufficiency of rational knowledge to fathom
the nature of the world Kant started from knowledge as afact, which our consciousness affords
us, thus in this sense he proceededa
posteriori. But in this chapter, and also in my
work, “Ueber den Willen in der Natur,” I have sought to show what knowledge is in itsnature and origin, something
secondary, designed for individual ends; whence it follows that
itmust beinsufficient to
fathom the nature of the world. Thus so far I have reached the same
goala priori. But one never
knows anything wholly and completely until one has gone right round
it for that purpose, and has got back to it from the opposite side
from which one [pg 029] started. Therefore also, in the case of the
important fundamental knowledge here considered, one must not
merely go from the intellect to the knowledge of the world, as Kant
has done, but also from the world, taken as given, to the
intellect, as I have undertaken here. Then this physiological
consideration, in the wider sense, becomes the supplement of that
ideological, as the French say, or, more accurately, transcendental
consideration.In the above, in order not to break the thread of the
exposition, I have postponed the explanation of one point which I
touched upon. It was this, that in proportion as, in the ascending
series of animals, the intellect appears ever more developed and
complete,knowledgealways
separates itself more distinctly fromwill, and thereby becomes purer. What
is essential upon this point will be found in my work, “Ueber den Willen in der Natur,” under
the heading, “Pflanzenphysiologie” (p. 68-72 of the second, and 74-77 of the third edition),
to which I refer, in order to avoid repetition, and merely add here
a few remarks. Since the plant possesses neither irritability nor
sensibility, but the will objectifies itself in it only as plastic
or reproductive power, it has neither muscle nor nerve. In the
lowest grades of the animal kingdom, in zoophites, especially in
polyps, we cannot as yet distinctly recognise the separation of
these two constituent parts, but still we assume their existence,
though in a state of fusion; because we perceive movements which
follow, not, as in the case of plants, upon mere stimuli, but upon
motives,i.e., in consequence
of a certain apprehension. Now in proportion as, in the ascending
series of animals, the nervous and muscular systemsseparateever more distinctly from each
other, till in the vertebrate animals, and most completely in man,
the former divides into an organic and a cerebral nervous system,
and of these the latter again develops into the excessively
complicated apparatus of the cerebrum and cerebellum, spinal
marrow, cerebral and spinal nerves, sensory and motor nerve
fascicles, of which only [pg 030] the cerebrum, together with the
sensory nerves depending upon it, and the posterior spinal nerve
fascicles are intended for theapprehension of the
motivefrom the external world, while all the
other parts are intended for thetransmissionof the motive to the
muscles in which the will manifests itself directly; in the same
proportion does themotiveseparate ever more distinctly inconsciousnessfrom theact of willwhich it calls forth, thus
theideafrom thewill; and thereby theobjectivityof consciousness constantly
increases, for the ideas exhibit themselves ever more distinctly
and purely in it. These twoseparationsare, however, really only
one and the same, which we have here considered from two sides, the
objective and the subjective, or first in the consciousness of
other things and then in self-consciousness. Upon the degree of
this separation ultimately depends the difference and the gradation
of intellectual capacity, both between different kinds of animals
and between individual human beings; thus it gives the standard for
the intellectual completeness of these beings. For the clearness of
the consciousness of the external world, the objectivity of the
perception, depends upon it. In the passage referred to above I
have shown that the brute only perceives things so far as they
aremotivesfor its will, and
that even the most intelligent of the brutes scarcely overstep
these limits, because their intellect is too closely joined to the
will from which it has sprung. On the other hand, even the
stupidest man comprehends things in some degreeobjectively; for he recognises not
merely what they are with reference to him, but also something of
what they are with reference to themselves and to other things. Yet
in the case of very few does this reach such a degree that they are
in a position to examine and judge of anything purelyobjectively; but “that must I do, that
must I say, that must I believe,” is the goal to which on every
occasion their thought hastens in a direct line, and at which their
understanding at once finds welcome rest. For thinking is as
unendurable to [pg 031] the weak head as the lifting of a burden to
the weak arm; therefore both hasten to set it down. The objectivity
of knowledge, and primarily of perceptive knowledge, has
innumerable grades, which depend upon the energy of the intellect
and its separation from the will, and the highest of which
isgenius, in which the
comprehension of the external world becomes so pure and objective
that to it even more reveals itself directly in the individual
thing than the individual thing itself, namely, the nature of its
wholespecies,i.e., its Platonic Idea; which is
brought about by the fact that in this case the will entirely
vanishes from consciousness. Here is the point at which the present
investigation, starting from physiological grounds, connects itself
with the subject of our third book, the metaphysics of the
beautiful, where æsthetic comprehension proper, which, in a high
degree, is peculiar to genius alone, is fully considered as the
condition of pure,i.e.,
perfectly will-less, and on that account completely objective
knowledge. According to what has been said, the rise of
intelligence, from the obscurest animal consciousness up to that of
man, is a progressiveloosening of the intellect
from the will, which appears complete, although
only as an exception, in thegenius. Therefore genius may be defined as the highest grade of
theobjectivityof knowledge.
The condition of this, which so seldom occurs, is a decidedly
larger measure of intelligence than is required for the service of
the will, which constitutes its basis; it is accordingly this free
surplus which first really properly comes to know the world,i.e., comprehends it perfectlyobjectively, and now paints pictures,
composes poems, and thinks in accordance with this
comprehension.[pg 032]Chapter XXIII.3On The Objectification
Of The Will In Unconscious Nature.That the will which we find within us does not proceed, as
philosophy has hitherto assumed, first from knowledge, and indeed
is a mere modification of it, thus something secondary, derived,
and, like knowledge itself, conditioned by the brain; but that it
is thepriusof knowledge, the
kernel of our nature, and that original force itself which forms
and sustains the animal body, in that it carries out both its
unconscious and its conscious functions;—this is the first step in
the fundamental knowledge of my metaphysics. Paradoxical as it even
now seems to many that the will in itself is without knowledge, yet
the scholastics in some way already recognised and confessed it;
for Jul. Cæs. Vaninus (that well-known sacrifice to fanaticism and
priestly fury), who was thoroughly versed in their philosophy, says
in his “Amphitheatro,” p. 181:
“Voluntas potentia cœca est, ex scholasticorum
opinione.” That, further, it is that same will
which in the plant forms the bud in order to develop the leaf and
the flower out of it; nay, that the regular form of the crystal is
only the trace which its momentary effort has left behind, and that
in general, as the true and only αυτοματον, in the proper sense of
the word, it lies at the foundation of all the forces of
unorganised nature, plays, acts, in all their multifarious
phenomena, imparts power to their laws, and even in the crudest
mass manifests itself as gravity;—this insight is the second step
in that fundamental knowledge, and is [pg 033] brought about by
further reflection. But it would be the grossest misunderstanding
to suppose that this is a mere question of a word to denote an
unknown quantity. It is rather the most real of all real knowledge
which is here expressed in language. For it is the tracing back of
that which is quite inaccessible to our immediate knowledge, and
therefore in its essence foreign and unknown to us, which we denote
by the wordsforce of nature,
to that which is known to us most accurately and intimately, but
which is yet only accessible to us in our own being and directly,
and must therefore be carried over from this to other phenomena. It
is the insight that what is inward and original in all the changes
and movements of bodies, however various they may be, is in its
nature identical; that yet we have only one opportunity of getting
to know it more closely and directly, and that is in the movements
of our own body. In consequence of this knowledge we must call
itwill. It is the insight that
that which acts and strives in nature, and exhibits itself in ever
more perfect phenomena, when it has worked itself up so far that
the light of knowledge falls directly upon it,i.e., when it has attained to the
state of self-consciousness—exists as thatwill, which is what is most intimately
known to us, and therefore cannot be further explained by anything
else, but rather affords the explanation of all other things. It is
accordingly thething in itselfso far as this can ever be reached by knowledge. Consequently
it is that which must express itself in some way in everything in
the world, for it is the inner nature of the world and the kernel
of all phenomena.As my essay, “Ueber den Willen in der
Natur