Erhalten Sie Zugang zu diesem und mehr als 300000 Büchern ab EUR 5,99 monatlich.
Essential illustrated guide to key ideas of political thought. Philosophers have always asked fundamental and disturbing questions about politics. Plato and Aristotle debated the merits of democracy. The origins of society, the state and government authority were issues addressed by Hobbes, Rousseau, Hegel, Marx and many other philosophers. Introducing Political Philosophy explains the central concepts of this intriguing branch of philosophy and presents the major political theorists from Plato to Foucault. How did governments get started? Why should they be obeyed? Could we live without them? How much power should they have? Is freedom a right? Which is the best form of government? In the wake of consumerism and postmodernism, our need for a better grasp of political ideas is greater than ever. Dave Robinson's account of this complex subject is always clear, informative and accompanied by the entertainingly inventive illustrations of Judy Groves.
Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:
Seitenzahl: 117
Veröffentlichungsjahr: 2014
Das E-Book (TTS) können Sie hören im Abo „Legimi Premium” in Legimi-Apps auf:
Published by Icon Books Ltd, Omnibus Business Centre, 39–41 North Road, London N7 9DPEmail: [email protected]
ISBN: 978-184831-203-6
Text copyright © 2012 Icon Books Ltd
Illustrations copyright © 2012 Icon Books Ltd
The author and illustrator has asserted their moral rights
Originating editor: Richard Appignanesi
No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, or by any means, without prior permission in writing from the publisher.
Cover
Title Page
Copyright
Questions
Back to Basics
Natural Communities
Society and State
What is Political Philosophy
Origins in Ancient Greece
The City State of Athens
The Duties of Citizens
Direct Democracy
Asking Questions
The Sophists
Glaucon’s View of Society
Beehives and Workers
The Pure Form of the State
Government by Experts
Relative Knowledge
The Ship of Fools
Is Democracy Still Best
Aristotle and Teleology
The “Good’” Man and the Citizen
Pragmatic Reason
Aristotle’s Politics
Economic Equality
Human Nature and Beliefs
What are Ideologies?
The Ideology of Essentialism
How Free Are We?
The Effects of Evolution
What Does Evolution Prove?
Humans as Selfish Co-operators
Game Theory
Co-operators or Competitors?
Who’s Right About Human Nature?
Life Without Governments?
Politics After Aristotle
Ancient Anarchists
Roman Stoics and Early Christians
Christian Dualism
St Augustine’s City of God
The Theology of St Aquinas
“Natural” Law
The Renaissance
Machiavelli’s Prince
State Morality
Cynic or Realist?
Hobbes and Cromwell
The Science of Man
Psychological Egoists
The State of Nature
The Prisoners’ Dilemma
The Way Out
Enforceable Coercion
Sovereign Power
Absolute Monarchies
Problems with the Hobbesian View
Natural Selfishness
John Locke
Another State of Nature
Locke’s Natural Laws
Definition of Properly
The Right of Inequality
The Problem of Vendettas
The Advantages of Society
Divine Right
Governments and Citizens
Minimal Government
Changing Governments
Rebels and Regimes
Separation of Powers
Who Can Vote?
Consent or Subservience
Hume’s Criticism
Rousseau’s Political Philosophy
Civilization and Human Nature
Pre-social State of Nature
Property and Law
Natural Education
Freedom and Society
The Assembly
The General Will
Perfect Citizens and Backsliders
The Contract and the Legislator
Politics as Ethics
Corsica and Poland
State Morality
The French Revolution
The Birth of French Socialism
What is Socialism?
Charles Fourier’s Universal Harmony
Owen’s Utopian Socialism
Small-scale Democracies
Anarchism
Liberty Without Property?
Anarchist Social Morality
Hegel’s Political Philosophy
The Philosophy of Right
Citizens and the Organic State
The Constitution
The All-Powerful State
Hegel’s Metaphysics
The Dialectic
Rational Freedom and Progress
Criticism of Hegel’s State
Edmund Burke’s Conservatism
Paine’s Rights of Man
The Human Rights Issue
Right and Left Hegelians
Economic Determinism
The Inevitability of Capitalism
Wicked Capitalists
Congealed Labour
The Function of Ideologies
The Spectre of Communism
The Radiant Future
Fact or Prophecy?
Class and the State
A Stateless Society
Revolution Delayed
Developments of Marxism
Gramsci’s Theory of Hegemony
Our Political Ideology
Origins of Liberalism
The Marketplace
Free Enterprise and Equality
Contracts, Constitutions and Tolerance
What is the Use of Voting?
The Distribution Problem
Bentham’s Utilitarianism
A Science of Morals
The Free-Enterprise Market
Calculating Consequences
Useful to Government Policy
Blind Spots of Utilitarianism
Mill’s Utilitarian Reply
Qualifying the Majority
Representation by the Educated
In Defence of Democracy
Modem Utilitarianism
Rights and Minority Interests
Distribution and Equality
Nozick’s Political Philosophy
Equality of Opportunity
The Minimal State
Rawls’ Thought Experiment
Rawlsian Society
Totalitarian States
Are Philosophers to Blame?
Is Pluralist Society Best?
The Limits on Freedom
Why Should We Obey?
Communitarian Aristotelians
Postmodernist Politics
Knowledge and Power
Environmental Politics
Feminist Politics
Consumers and Citizens
Democracy by Choice
Further Reading
About the author and artist
Acknowledgements
Index
Political philosophers ask questions about individuals, communities, society, the law, political power, the State, and about how they all relate.
▶ Is it possible or desirable to say what human beings are “really like”?
▶ What is society? Is it something more than the people who live in it? Or was the British Prime Minister Mrs Thatcher right to say “There is no such thing as society”?
▶ What is the State? Is it an artificial construct or something that has naturally evolved?
▶ How free can the State allow individual citizens to be? Are there good moral reasons why citizens are obliged to obey the law? To what extent does the State have the right to punish those who disobey its commands?
▶ Is democracy the best form of government?
▶ Should the State be interested in furthering economic equality? If so, should it be allowed to interfere with other people’s private property?
DO WE NEED GOVERNMENTS AT ALL?
Many political philosophers begin by concentrating on individuals. After all, societies and states are made up of individuals first, and governments must come after. Are political institutions simply the end result of attempts to fulfil the essential and universal needs of individuals? But what if we have no real knowledge about the needs and purposes of human beings? Besides, we aren’t just dropped into society with all the ready-made capacities that make us human.
THERE CAN BE NO DOUBT THAT SOCIETY MAKES US.EVEN OUR MOST “PRIVATE” THOUGHTS DERIVE FROM LINGUISTIC RESOURCES THAT AREN’T OUR OWN.BUT EVEN THOUGH WE MIGHT ALL BE DERIVATIVE “SOCIAL PRODUCTS”, NONE OF US FEEL WE’RE JUST ROBOTS.PARADOXICALLY, WE ARE MADE BY SOMETHING THAT WE FEEL WE HAVE THE RIGHT (AND DUTY) TO QUESTION.
The word “community” suggests something immediate, local and praiseworthy. Political philosophers think of communities as small groups of people with shared values who enjoy solidarity with little need of laws or hierarchical chains of command.
THE EXISTENCE OF COMMUNITIES SUGGESTS THAT HUMAN BEINGS CAN BE SOCIAL WITHOUT NECESSARILY BEING “POLITICALLY GOVERNED”.SO WHAT’S “SOCIETY”, THEN?SOCIETIES ARE LARGER THAN COMMUNITIES AND HELD TOGETHER BY COMPLEX SYSTEMS OF RULES, CUSTOMS AND INSTITUTIONS.
17th-century political philosophers made distinctions between free associations of individuals – societies, perhaps agreed on by some form of “contract” between individuals – and States, which are constituted by specific hierarchical power structures and the threat of coercion.
Is it possible that we are all “social animals” but not necessarily political ones? Where is the evidence for non-political societies? Or is this an idealistic fantasy? Some philosophers believe that distinctions made between societies and States only lead to confusion. Societies can only exist if they are political. Power – and who has it – are features of human life that never go away.
THE “STATE” IS DEFINED AS AN AREA OF TERRITORY WITH AN ORGANIZED LEGAL SYSTEM AND A GOVERNMENT THAT HAS A “LEGITIMATE” MONOPOLY OF FORCE OVER ITS CITIZENS.MODERN STATES HAVE ENORMOUS AND OFTEN INTRUSIVE AUTHORITY…THAT’S WHY PHILOSOPHERS ENDLESSLY REDEFINE WORDS LIKE “CONSENT” “AUTHORITY” AND “OBLIGATION”.
Most modern philosophers accept that moral and political propositions have no factual or logical status. Hence, it is impossible to prescribe what States should be or define what ought to be our relationship to them. Providing definitive answers to political problems must be ruled out.
ALL THAT PHILOSOPHERS CAN DO IS ANALYZE AND MAKE MORE PRECISE THE CONCEPTS WE USE IN EVERYDAY SPEECH – SUCH AS “POWER”, “LAW” “RIGHTS” AND SO ON. BUT POLITICS IS A VERY PRACTICAL AND IMPORTANT REALITY… WE EXPECT ADVICE FROM PHILOSOPHERS, NOT MERELY “ANALYSIS OF CONCEPTS”.
But political philosophy is as ideological as any other kind of discourse. We accept from it what agrees with our normal core beliefs and values. This is why all political concepts are always “essentially contrasted”.
The first people to write about political philosophy were the ancient Greeks. To begin with they were “stateless” semi-nomadic tribes who finally settled all over the coastal regions of the Aegean and Mediterranean.
WE WERE WARRIORS RULED BY WARLORDS. WE PLACED A HIGH VALUE ON COMRADESHIP, LOYALTY AND COURAGE. DIFFERENT WARRING TRIBES THEN CONGREGATED INTO LARGER UNITS FOR DEFENCE PURPOSES AND GRADUALLY ESTABLISHED “CITY STATES” LIKE ATHENS AND SPARTA.
The “Polis” or City State was usually small and independent, and each one was ruled by its own unique kind of government.
The most interesting and influential “Polis” was Athens, which experienced all sorts of governments. Political power had originally rested in the hands of a kind of aristocracy, similar to a tribal council, but gradually the citizen body itself acquired more and more power, and eventually ruled Athens between 461 and 322 BC.
ATHENS BECAME FAMOUS FOR ITS UNIQUE FORM OF DIRECT PARTICIPATORY DEMOCRACY. IT INVOLVED ALL OF ITS 50,000 ADULT MALE CITIZENS. BUT NOT WOMEN, SLAVES OR FOREIGNERS!
Being an Athenian “citizen” was a serious business, involving duties as well as rights.
WE DO NOT SAY THAT A MAN WHO TAKES NO INTEREST IN POLITICS IS A MAN WHO MINDS HIS OWN BUSINESS; WE SAY THAT HE HAS NO BUSINESS HERE AT ALL. THE POPULAR ASSEMBLY (I.E. THE “GOVERNMENT”), MADE UP OF ALL ADULT MALE CITIZENS, MET AT REGULAR INTERVALS TO DECIDE ON MATTERS OF STATE. SO ATHENS WAS GOVERNED BY AMATEURS.
The population was small enough for this kind of “pure” democracy to work, and most Athenians seemed to have been immensely proud of their State. They identified with it so completely that it was virtually impossible for any of them to imagine a life outside it.
Athenians fought alongside each other in battle and were more “tribal” than we are now. Their social and political world was very different from ours. They had little conception of “the individual” as something separate from “the citizen” and only very hazy notions of private rights. Society and State were indistinguishable.
FOR MODERN PHILOSOPHERS AND HISTORIANS THIS IS A MAJOR HEADACHE. MANY ANCIENT GREEK WORDS ARE ALMOST IMPOSSIBLE TO TRANSLATE, SO DEEPLY EMBEDDED ARE THEY IN THIS UNIQUE CULTURE. THIS HASN’T STOPPED MOST OF US FROM HAVING FIRM OPINIONS ABOUT THIS ANCIENT STATE RUN BY ITS OWN CITIZENS. Some, like Rousseau, Hegel and other modern “communitarians” think that many of its values and beliefs are exemplary, whereas other “liberals” express grave doubts about its notions of absolute citizenship.
Athenian philosophers were argumentative. They were fascinated by debate and ideas, and invented the subject we now call “philosophy”. This means that they were “modern” because they were critical. They refused to accept religious or traditional explanations for anything and asked disturbingly original questions that no one had ever thought of asking before – especially about “society”, “morality” and “politics” (which derives from the Greek word Polis).
WE EVEN SPECULATED ABOUT WHAT LIFE MIGHT HAVE BEEN LIKE BEFORE “SOCIETY” BEGAN. AS MORE BECAME KNOWN ABOUT STRANGE PLACES LIKE EGYPT AND PERSIA, WE WONDERED HOW “NATURAL” OR “ARTIFICIAL” SOCIETIES WERE. ATHENIANS WERE BEGINNING TO THINK OF THEMSELVES AS INDIVIDUALS, AS WELL AS SOCIAL BEINGS, AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY WAS BEGINNING.
Plato (c. 428–347 BC) was the first philosopher to record many of these theoretical discussions about politics. In his book The Republic, Socrates, Plato’s old teacher and friend, discusses the true nature of “justice” with his Sophist philosopher friends. (This “embedded” word “justice” means something like “behaving as you should”.) The Sophists were itinerant, radical thinkers who sold their services as tutors to wealthy families and specialized in teaching rhetoric.
THE SOPHIST THRASYMACHUS BEGINS BY INSISTING THAT ALL GOVERNMENTS ARE FRAUDULENT. EACH TYPE OF GOVERNMENT ENACTS LAWS THAT ARE IN ITS OWN INTEREST: A DEMOCRACY, DEMOCRATIC LAWS; A TYRANNY, TYRANNICAL ONES; AND SO ON. “RIGHT” IS MERELY THE INTEREST OF THE ESTABLISHED GOVERNMENT. IN OTHER WORDS, ALL GOVERNMENTS WHO CLAIM A “NATURAL” RIGHT TO RULE ARE ALWAYS DISGUISING THE FACT THAT THEY RULE IN THE INTERESTS OF ONE PARTICULAR GROUP.
Another Sophist, Glaucon, insists that societies exist only because human behaviour has always to be restrained by law.
WITHOUT LAWS, HUMAN BEINGS ALWAYS REVERT TO BARBARISM, AND SO EVERYONE SUFFERS. THE ONLY REMEDY IS FOR EVERYONE TO AGREE CONTRACTUALLY TO OBEY A FEW COMPULSORY MORAL RULES. SO IT IS ARTIFICIAL LAWS, NOT CO-OPERATIVE INSTINCTS, THAT CONSTITUTE SOCIETIES.
Most Sophists insisted that morality, society, the state and governments are always the artificial creations of human beings – there is nothing at all “natural” or “organic” about them.
Plato rejected this subversive scepticism. Both society and the State are natural, inevitable and benign. His mouthpiece “Socrates” rarely engages in real debate, but hammers away constantly at two ideas – that ruling is a skill, and that all human beings have a specific and prescribed natural function.
SOME PEOPLE ARE JUST SIMPLY BORN RULERS, AND THE REST OF US MUST REMAIN THEIR OBEDIENT WORKERS!
Plato was a communitarian and his ideal society is like a harmonious beehive in which everybody knows their role, and this is what “justice” or “behaving as you should” is all about.
Plato was an aristocrat, so his ideal hierarchical society of born rulers and submissive workers isn’t much of a surprise. But his advocacy of this orderly beehive rests on more than simple class loyalty. Plato was wholly convinced by the Pythagorean vision of mathematics. Numbers are “pure” – uncontaminated by the world, independent of human desires, eternal, incorruptible and always true. 2+2 will always equal 4, regardless of whether human beings exist or not.
ALL REAL KNOWLEDGE HAS TO BE LIKE NUMBERS – PERMANENT AND TRANSCENDENT. ALL WE SEE AROUND US ARE FEEBLE, TRANSIENT “COPIES” OF THE MORE REAL “FORMS” MYSTERIOUSLY ENCODED INTO THE UNIVERSE AND HUMAN MINDS.
Plato’s idealist metaphysics of “pure Forms” is the result of a whole series of linguistic confusions. It meant that there had to be a perfect “Form” for “The State”. His Republic is largely concerned with the education of the State’s rulers called “The Guardians” – an élite group of political experts who know all there is to know about “The Perfect State”, composed of a hierarchy of metals.
THE “GOLD” GUARDIANS RULE OVER EVERYONE. THERE ARE “SILVER” ADMINISTRATORS … AND BELOW THEM, “BRONZE” AND “IRON” WORKERS WHO ALL HAPPILY ACCEPT THEIR PLACE IN OUR STABLE, SELF-PERPETUATING AND PERFECT STATE.