1,99 €
Niedrigster Preis in 30 Tagen: 1,99 €
In "Introduction to the Philosophy and Writings of Plato," Thomas Taylor presents a comprehensive analysis of Plato's philosophical thought and literary contributions. Taylor deftly navigates the intricacies of Plato's dialogues, emphasizing his allegorical style, dialectical method, and the profound moral and metaphysical concepts that permeate his work. This study is situated within the broader context of 18th-century Neoplatonism, which heavily influenced Taylor's interpretations, allowing readers to appreciate the timeless relevance of Plato's ideas in contemporary philosophical discourse. Thomas Taylor, often hailed as the "Plato of the West," was a pivotal figure in the revival of Neoplatonism and classical scholarship during the late 18th and early 19th centuries. His passion for the philosophical traditions of antiquity stemmed from his extensive studies of ancient texts, often infused with his own mystical and metaphysical insights. Taylor's dedication to making Plato's ideas accessible reflects his broader aim of reviving classical philosophy and its ethical underpinnings, providing a vital resource for both scholars and students alike. This book is highly recommended for anyone seeking a deeper understanding of Plato's philosophical contributions. By contextualizing his thoughts within both ancient and modern frameworks, Taylor's work serves as an essential guide for philosophers, historians, and literary enthusiasts alike, illuminating the enduring significance of Plato's writings and their impact on subsequent thought. In this enriched edition, we have carefully created added value for your reading experience: - A succinct Introduction situates the work's timeless appeal and themes. - The Synopsis outlines the central plot, highlighting key developments without spoiling critical twists. - A detailed Historical Context immerses you in the era's events and influences that shaped the writing. - A thorough Analysis dissects symbols, motifs, and character arcs to unearth underlying meanings. - Reflection questions prompt you to engage personally with the work's messages, connecting them to modern life. - Hand‐picked Memorable Quotes shine a spotlight on moments of literary brilliance. - Interactive footnotes clarify unusual references, historical allusions, and archaic phrases for an effortless, more informed read.
Das E-Book können Sie in Legimi-Apps oder einer beliebigen App lesen, die das folgende Format unterstützen:
Veröffentlichungsjahr: 2019
Uniting scholarship with spiritual ambition, Thomas Taylor’s Introduction to the Philosophy and Writings of Plato presents Platonism as a disciplined ascent from opinion to intellect, guiding readers through dialogue, myth, and mathematics toward a unified vision of reality in which ethical, political, and cosmological questions cohere, and in which the careful reading of Plato’s dramatic art becomes inseparable from the cultivation of a life oriented to intelligible principles rather than to the flux of appearances, illuminating how argument, symbolism, and education converge in the pursuit of wisdom.
This work is a philosophical prolegomenon accompanying Taylor’s English translations of Plato, prepared in the early nineteenth century amid renewed British interest in classical antiquity. An influential English Neoplatonist, Taylor aimed to transmit the Platonic tradition to a wider public, drawing on late antique commentators and emphasizing continuity between Plato and his successors. The result belongs to the genre of interpretive introduction: not a neutral encyclopedia entry, but a guide shaped by a clear lineage. Readers encounter an essay poised between scholarship and advocacy, intended to prepare them for the dialogues while framing how those dialogues might best be approached.
At its core, the book offers a map of Plato’s corpus and methods, sketching how dramatic setting, dialectical argument, and mythic narrative cooperate in educating the soul. Taylor’s voice is confident and didactic, often expansive in expression, yet attentive to technical distinctions that matter for close reading. The mood is earnest rather than ironic, encouraging patience with difficult passages and sensitivity to symbolic layers. The experience is that of a learned companion who orients without summarizing every dialogue, suggesting pathways and priorities for study while insisting that form and philosophy in Plato are inseparable.
Taylor highlights themes that recur across Platonic thought: the hierarchy from sensible to intelligible realities, the role of mathematics in purifying the mind, the ethical transformation required for philosophical vision, and the civic dimension of wisdom. He underscores the significance of myth not as ornament but as a vehicle for conveying truths that exceed discursive analysis. The result is a portrait of Platonism as both rigorous and contemplative, one that refuses to separate metaphysics from practice. Readers are invited to consider how reflection on the Good, Soul, and Cosmos shapes judgment, character, and communal life.
A distinctive feature of Taylor’s approach is his reliance on the ancient exegetical tradition, especially later Platonists who systematized relationships among the dialogues. Without collapsing Plato into a single doctrine, he presents a structured vista in which terms, methods, and aims interlock. This orientation foregrounds ascent, purification, and participation as guiding motifs. It also places Plato in conversation with Pythagorean inheritance and with commentators such as Plotinus and Proclus, whose analyses inform Taylor’s hermeneutic. The reader thus receives not only an introduction to Plato, but also an entryway into the living reception history that shaped early modern engagement with Platonism.
For contemporary readers, the book matters because it models an integrative vision of knowledge at a time when specialization fragments inquiry. It prompts questions about the bonds between reason and imagination, argument and symbol, scientific explanation and metaphysical orientation. It invites reconsideration of education as the formation of attention rather than the accumulation of information. It also shows how a translator’s commitments shape the horizon of interpretation. Agree or disagree with Taylor’s Neoplatonic emphasis, one learns to approach classic texts with humility, curiosity, and the awareness that methods of reading are never philosophically neutral.
Approached as a companion rather than a verdict, this introduction offers a disciplined way to begin or renew a study of Plato. Newcomers gain bearings about genres, aims, and obstacles; experienced readers meet a demanding, historically rooted framework that can challenge assumptions. The prose rewards unhurried reading, and the structure encourages returning to themes as one moves through the dialogues. While tethered to a specific intellectual tradition, the book leaves space for readers to test its claims in encounter with the texts themselves, turning orientation into practice and study into a sustained philosophical exercise.
Thomas Taylor’s Introduction to the Philosophy and Writings of Plato serves as a structured guide to Plato’s corpus and the Platonic tradition. It explains the aim, scope, and method of studying Plato, situating the dialogues within a comprehensive philosophical system. Drawing on late antique commentators such as Plotinus, Iamblichus, and Proclus, Taylor outlines the theological, physical, ethical, and logical dimensions he sees articulated across the works. He clarifies key terms, sets expectations about Plato’s dramatic and often symbolic style, and frames the dialogues as progressive exercises designed to elevate the reader from opinion to knowledge. The introduction’s purpose is to prepare readers for coherent, systematic engagement with Plato.
The work begins with a concise account of Plato’s life and intellectual context. It notes Plato’s apprenticeship under Socrates, his travels, and his contact with Pythagorean traditions, emphasizing how these shaped his philosophical interests. The foundation of the Academy is presented as institutionalizing a curriculum that united mathematics, dialectic, and ethics. Taylor characterizes the dialogues as dramatic compositions that combine inquiry and instruction, in which Socrates often functions as the central searcher. This biographical and historical framing leads to a general description of the dialogues’ pedagogical intent: to draw readers from everyday beliefs toward stable knowledge through testing, recollection, and philosophical purification.
Taylor then presents a classification of the dialogues by subject and function, distinguishing logical, ethical, political, physical, and theological works, as well as those of a mixed character. He notes the difference between exoteric texts and those intended for more advanced study, and he addresses the dramatic form that may conceal doctrinal structure. A tentative order for reading is proposed to cultivate the learner’s capacities step by step. The account emphasizes that each dialogue has a chief aim, and that the variety of styles—argument, myth, and example—serves coordinated educational ends. Chronological questions are treated as secondary to pedagogical progression.
A central section summarizes Platonic first principles. Taylor outlines a hierarchy beginning from the Good, or the One, beyond being and knowledge, followed by the intelligible order of Forms and the intellect that apprehends them. Soul mediates between intelligible and sensible realms, and nature orders the physical world according to formative causes. Participation explains how sensibles share in the Forms without exhausting them. Causality proceeds in a structured chain, and philosophical analysis employs triadic patterns of remaining, procession, and return. This metaphysical framework is presented as the key to interpreting the dialogues consistently, ensuring that particular arguments fit within a unified doctrine.
Plato’s theology is described as a graduated order of divine beings. Taylor distinguishes the supreme Good from the intellectual creator or Demiurge, and further identifies ranks that include gods, daemons, and heroes as mediators of providence. He explains how names of deities, myths, and rites function philosophically to signify intelligible realities. Providence, fate, and necessity are coordinated so that higher causes remain unconfounded with lower conditions. This hierarchical theism is presented as consistent with the dialogues’ language and with ancient interpretive traditions. The account clarifies the place of prayer, piety, and ritual within Platonic life without subordinating philosophical reason to symbol.
The introduction summarizes Platonic cosmology with particular attention to the Timaeus. Taylor sets out the formation of the universe as a living animal endowed with a world-soul, guided by intellect and proportion. He explains the receptacle, the geometric construction of the elements, and the harmonies that constitute the cosmic order. Time is described as the moving image of eternity, coordinating celestial motions with intelligible measure. The discussion distinguishes what proceeds by reason from what is permitted by necessity, and it situates physical explanations within the broader metaphysical scheme. Cosmology thus exemplifies how form, number, and purpose permeate the visible world.
The psychology and ethics of Plato follow from the same principles. Taylor presents the soul as immortal, self-moving, and capable of knowing the intelligible through recollection. He outlines the soul’s powers and the famous tripartition, relating these to education and civic life. Virtue is arranged in ascending orders: political virtues stabilize conduct, purifying virtues detach the soul from passions, and contemplative virtues align it with intellect; paradigmatic virtues emulate divine patterns. Justice is harmony, and law gives form to communal virtue. The ethical end is assimilation to God as far as possible, achieved through purification, intellectual discipline, and rightly ordered desire.
Taylor then expounds Plato’s method. Dialectic is the summit of philosophical practice, employing definition, division, and demonstration to ascend from sensibles to intelligibles and finally to the Good. Mathematics serves as a preparatory path, training the mind to contemplate immutable relations. Myths are treated as pedagogical instruments that veil and reveal truths suited to the audience, and the interpreter is cautioned against purely literal readings. Socratic irony is noted as a rhetorical strategy that tests interlocutors and readers. The result is a unified approach to argument, symbol, and study that safeguards doctrinal coherence while accommodating multiple levels of understanding.
The introduction concludes with practical guidance for students of Plato. It recommends a graduated reading sequence, beginning with dialogues that shape ethical character and self-knowledge, proceeding through mathematical and political studies, and culminating in works central to metaphysics and theology. The aim is steady purification of intellect and will, supported by disciplined habits and reverent attention to first principles. Taylor closes by presenting Plato’s writings as a complete philosophical education ordered to truth and the good life. The overall message is that careful, traditional interpretation enables the dialogues to function as an integrated path from opinion to wisdom and, ultimately, to the Good.
Thomas Taylor’s Introduction to the Philosophy and Writings of Plato accompanied his complete English translation of Plato, issued in London in 1804. The work arose in Georgian Britain amid the upheavals of the 1790s, when the metropolis was a hub of print culture, learned societies, and ideological conflict. Taylor, an independent scholar outside the universities, worked among London’s booksellers and drew on the British Museum’s collections to consult Greek editions and commentaries. Britain’s posture of global war and domestic surveillance shaped the intellectual climate: metaphysical inquiry and appeals to ancient civic virtue appeared as counterweights to volatility. Taylor’s London thus supplied both the resources and the anxieties that framed his Platonic project.
The French Revolution of 1789, followed by the Reign of Terror (1793–1794), catalyzed Britain’s political crisis. William Pitt’s ministry prosecuted suspected radicals in the Treason Trials of 1794, and Parliament passed the Seditious Meetings and Treasonable Practices Acts (1795) and later the Combination Acts (1799–1800) to curb agitation. Loyalist associations flourished, while reformist clubs were surveilled or closed. Taylor’s Introduction echoes this context through Plato’s cautions about demagogy and civic disorder in the Republic and Laws. By foregrounding the philosophical governance of reason and virtue, he frames Plato as a corrective to contemporary faction, implying that only an educated, hieratic wisdom can stabilize polities convulsed by revolutionary passions.
The Napoleonic Wars (1799–1815) militarized British life and disrupted continental scholarly exchange. Naval battles—Copenhagen (1801), Trafalgar (1805)—secured Britain’s sea lanes, yet travel to European libraries was precarious, and access to newly edited Greek texts was uneven. Taylor’s reliance on earlier Stephanus editions and London holdings reflects wartime constraints on philology. The patriotic celebration of ancient civic models also intensified: public discourse mined Greece and Rome for exempla of fortitude and law. Taylor’s Introduction engages this mood by presenting Plato’s ethics and politics as a repertoire of civic discipline, elevating philosophical paideia over expediency and thereby offering a metaphysical ballast to a nation living under the strain of total war.
A surge of British philhellenism shaped the decades around Taylor’s work. Between 1801 and 1812 Lord Elgin removed sculptures from the Athenian Acropolis; Parliament purchased the Elgin Marbles for the British Museum in 1816, prompting heated debates about cultural patrimony and Greek excellence. The Greek War of Independence (1821–1829) mobilized British committees in London, and Lord Byron died at Missolonghi in 1824 while aiding the Greek cause. Taylor’s Introduction situates Plato within the grandeur of Hellenic religion and civic life, reinforcing an image of Greece as a moral and spiritual exemplar. His Platonic synthesis helped supply the educated public with a philosophical rationale for venerating, and politically supporting, Hellenic revival.
Late Georgian educational and religious arrangements conditioned classical study. Oxford and Cambridge maintained Anglican tests for degrees, excluding Dissenters until reforms in 1828 (Test and Corporation Acts repealed) and 1871 (university tests abolished), while Catholics gained emancipation in 1829. Greek philology advanced through figures like Richard Porson (1759–1808) at Cambridge, yet university classicism often prioritized technical grammar and Aristotelian logic. Working outside these institutions, Taylor promoted a theologically saturated Platonism, drawing on later Platonists to recover a sacral metaphysics. His Introduction thus diverged from confessional orthodoxy and narrow scholastic drill, advocating direct engagement with Plato’s Greek and a hieratic philosophy purporting to reunite ethics, politics, and theology.
Print culture, finance, and control of the press shaped Taylor’s enterprise. After Donaldson v. Beckett (1774) ended perpetual common-law copyright, competitive reprinting proliferated, and costly classics relied on subscriptions. The radical press boom of the early 1790s met repression after 1794 and under the Two Acts (1795), creating a cautious environment for speculative works. Taylor’s large 1804 Plato appeared by subscription in London, its heavy quartos demanding committed patrons from gentry, professionals, and curious artisans. The Introduction’s sweeping historical-theological argument used the prestige of classical scholarship to traverse a watchful public sphere, presenting Platonic doctrine as ancient wisdom rather than polemic, while nevertheless speaking to contemporary questions of authority and civic education.
The intellectual battleground that most decisively shaped Taylor’s Introduction pitted British empiricism and emergent utilitarian reform against a revived metaphysical Platonism. Following David Hume’s skepticism (A Treatise of Human Nature, 1739–1740; Enquiry, 1748), the Scottish Common Sense school (e.g., Thomas Reid, Essays on the Intellectual Powers, 1785) defended ordinary belief and perception, steering philosophy toward psychology and practical morals. Jeremy Bentham’s utilitarianism (An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, 1789) and political radicalism—articulated alongside Thomas Paine’s Rights of Man (1791–1792) and William Godwin’s Enquiry Concerning Political Justice (1793)—pressed for legal codification, transparency, and the maximization of welfare. Edmund Burke’s Reflections on the Revolution in France (1790) replied with a historical, prudential defense of tradition. Within this contested field, Taylor’s Introduction advances a countermodern settlement: Plato’s intelligible Forms, the tripartite soul, and a hierarchical cosmos culminate in a graded polity stewarded by intellectual and moral elites. Drawing on late antique Platonists—Plotinus (204/5–270), Iamblichus (c. 245–325), Proclus (412–485)—Taylor integrates ritual, myth, and theurgy as pedagogies of ascent, resisting the reduction of ethics to utility or sentiment. London institutions like the Royal Institution (founded 1799) showcased experimental science and public lectures, emblematic of a culture valorizing utility and demonstration; against this, Taylor rehabilitates contemplative science as the crown of public life. He turns Plato’s Republic, Laws, and Timaeus into an architectonic answer to materialism and political leveling, implying that policy must be rooted in metaphysical anthropology and divine order. Thus the Introduction mirrors concrete debates in 1790s–1800s Britain over the basis of authority, the aims of education, the legitimacy of democracy, and the status of religion in civic formation, positioning Platonism as a principled alternative to both revolutionary radicalism and pragmatic reform.
As social and political critique, the book exposes anxieties about mass opinion, expediency, and secular power by elevating philosophical rule and the training of character. It indicts the period’s utilitarian calculus and commercial priorities as insufficient for justice, echoing Plato’s rebukes of sophistry and appetitive governance. It also challenges confessional monopolies by proposing a pre-Christian, theologically robust civic wisdom grounded in Greek philosophy. In wartime Britain, with surveillance of associations and curtailed debate, the Introduction defends rigorous, truth-oriented deliberation over factional rhetoric. Its portrait of the rightly ordered soul and city functions as a rebuke to both demagogic populism and managerial technocracy, urging a morally aristocratic public culture.