The PHILOSOPHY OF FREEDOM of Rudolf Steiner a cure by Silvano Angelini - Silvano Angelini - E-Book

The PHILOSOPHY OF FREEDOM of Rudolf Steiner a cure by Silvano Angelini E-Book

Silvano Angelini

0,0
5,99 €

oder
-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

The Philosophy of Freedom is a magical text, because it activates thought, feeling and will, clears the field of any obstacle that may arise in life, giving everyone the opportunity to find their own direction freely. To the question: "What will remain of your work in a thousand years?" Answered "The Philosophy of Freedom" was Rudolf Steiner.

Das E-Book können Sie in Legimi-Apps oder einer beliebigen App lesen, die das folgende Format unterstützen:

EPUB
Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



Indice

INTRODUCTION

PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1894

PREFACE TO THE REVISED EDITION, 1918

THE PHILOSOPHY OF FREEDOM

KNOWLEDGE OF FREEDOM

1 - CONSCIOUS HUMAN ACTION

2 - THE FUNDAMENTAL URGE FOR KNOWLEDGE

3 - THINKING IN SERVICE OF UNDERSTANDING THE WORLD

4 - THE WORLD AS PERCEPTION

5 - THE ACT OF KNOWING THE WORLD

6 - HUMAN INDIVIDUALITY

7 - ARE THERE LIMITS TO KNOWLEDGE?

THE REALITY OF FREEDOM

8 - THE FACTORS OF LIFE

9 - THE IDEA OF FREEDOM

10 - PHILOSOPHY OF FREEDOM AND MONISM

11 - WORLD PURPOSE AND LIFE PURPOSE (Human destiny)

12 -MORAL IMAGINATION (DARWINISM AND MORALITY)

13 -THE VALUE OF LIFE (PESSIMISM AND OPTIMISM)

14 - INDIVIDUALITY AND GENUS

15 - Ultimate Questions

THE CONSEQUENCES OF MONISM

16 - 1st Addition 1918

17 - 2nd Addition 1918

FIRST APPENDIX 1918

On the cover "Widar" terracotta sculpture of Silvano Angelini

 

RUDOLF STEINERTHE PHILOSOPHY OF FREEDOMFUNDAMENTAL LINESFOR A MODERN WORLD CONCEPTIONResults of the observation of the soul according to

the method of natural sciences.Translation of Silvano AngeliniReview of Alison Steffen and Katherine Alexandra Clarknative English speaker 

RIMINIEDITRICE DODECAUREO GALLERY 2019

Information for the reader:

 the first edition of this method, which includes the numbering of the thoughts and the aid of graphic tables outside the text was made in Italian. We apologize to the English reader for the fact that the graphic tables (in which there are the original drawings) are written in Italian, and we gradually hope to translate into English.

We invite readers or scholars to report any error or to advise a better translation of the text, we warmly welcome any help; as far as criticism is concerned, we will try to look at it positively and treasure it, thanks for the collaboration,

Silvano Angelini 2019 

 

For the era of Michael 

We must eradicate all fear from the soulas well as the fear of what the future can bring to man.We must acquire serenity in allfeelings and sensations about the future.

We must look forward with absolute equanimitytowards everything that can come;and we must think thateverything that will come, will be given by onedirection of the world full of wisdom.

This is part of what we have to learn in this era:to know how to live with absolute trust,without any security in existence;confidence in the ever present help of the spiritual world.In truth, nothing will have value ifwe lack courage.We discipline our will and look for theinner awakeningevery morning and every night.

INTRODUCTIONThe task of this work is to try to be of help to the fasting reader of philosophy like me, highlighting with graphic illustrations some imaginative processes rich in the Philosophy of Freedom by Rudolf Steiner.

It is a task in continuous becoming like every inner growth that connects to an unveiling of the etheric.

I allowed myself: to introduce the "Preface to the I Edition of 1894" before the "Preface to the II Edition of 1918", for the simple reason that my intellectual faculties do not allow me to understand the second if I have not read and understood the first of 1894.

I wanted to proceed to the consecutive numbering of every single thought, because I personally found it helpful in the study of this work and useful in group work. Sometimes I felt the need to change number to help the meditation of a concept expressed in the text, even within a more complex sentence, so even after a comma, for the same reason I added italics and inverted commas. In the translation, given that in recent years the new media has broken down the boundaries and limits that the states placed to safeguard their territoriality, I decided to change some words of the text, in order not to hurt the susceptibility of distant people in space and belonging to other ethnic groups, religions, customs; and this not in the fatuous light of a protagonism, but to promote the dissemination of this work so precious for the evolution of humanity.

Silvano Angelini March 2011

In support of the importance of drawing, the author has expressed himself numerous times, I quote this passage:

"Maybe it's a difficult concept to understand; it would be good, however, if you tried to complete this representation with thought, but we can make it clearer with the help of a design." Lecture 11 / 12/1917 by R. Steiner (n.r.)

GRAPHIC TABLES should be interpreted as imaginative, non-exhaustive, not fixed, non-dogmatic suggestions that everyone can expand or reduce in their own soul with the utmost freedom. n.r.

In appendix 66 color GRAPHIC TABLES.

 

ABBREVIATIONS and various

 

Author's Prefaces

PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1894

1) In the following, in all essentials, is reproduced what served as a kind of preface to the first edition of this book.
2) I place it as an appendix because it conveys the kind of thoughts that occupied me when I wrote the book twenty-five years ago, rather than having any direct bearing on the content.
3) Since the opinion crops up, again and again, I do not want to omit it altogether and because of my writings on the science of the spirit, I have to suppress some of my earlier writings. -
4) Our age is one in which truth must be sought in the depths of human nature.

Only the very first opening sentences (in the first edition) are left out here, because to-day they seem to me to be quite irrelevant; whereas saying the rest seems as necessary today as it did then, despite the prevalent scientific trend of thought, and in fact just because of it.

5) Of Schiller’s two well-known paths:

“Truth seek we both –

in outer life you;

I in the heart within.

By both can Truth alike be found.

If the eye is healthy,

meets the Creator without;

If the heart is healthy,

it mirrors the world within..”

Johann Christoph Friedrich von Schiller

Translation Italian graphic:

We both seek truth

6) Our present age prefers the second.
7) A truth which comes to us from outside always bears the stamp of uncertainty.
8) We trust only which appears to us inwardly as truth.
9) Only truth can bring us certainty in developing our individual powers.
10) In someone tormented by doubts, the powers are weakened. In a world that appears to him as an enigma, he can find no goal for his creative powers.
11) No longer do we merely want to believe; we want to know.
12) Belief demands acknowledgement of truths which are not quite clear to us. But what is not clearly recognized goes against what is individual in us, which wants to experience everything in the depth of its being.
13) Only the kind of knowing which satisfies us is not submitted to no outer norm, but springs from the inner life-experience of our personality.
14) Nor do we want a kind of knowledge which has become hardened into formulas and is stored away, valid for all time.
15) Each of us considers himself justified in proceeding from his immediate experience, from the facts he knows, and from there ascending to gain knowledge of the whole universe.
16) We strive for certainty in knowledge, but each in his own way.
17) Our scientific teachings, too, should no longer take a form that implies their acceptance to be a compulsion.
18) Today no one should give a scientific work a title like that which Fichte once gave a book: “A Pellucid Report for the Broader Public concerning the Essential Nature of Recent Philosophies. An Attempt to Compel Readers to Understand.”
19) Today no one is to be compelled to understand.
20) We demand neither acceptance nor agreement from anyone unless his own particular, individual need urges him to the view in question.
21) Today we do not want to cram knowledge into even an immature human being, the child; rather we should seek to develop his faculties so that he no longer needs to be compelled to understand, but will understand.
22) I am under no illusion concerning these characteristics of my time.
23) I know how much of a stereotypical attitude, lacking all individuality, prevails everywhere.
24) But I also know that many of my contemporaries strive to order their lives in the direction I have indicated.
25) To them I would like to dedicate this book. It is not meant to be the “only possible” way that leads to truth, but it describes a path taken by one whose heart is set upon truth.
26) This book at first leads the reader into abstract regions, where thought must have sharp outlines if it is to reach secure positions.
27) But the reader is also led out of these arid concepts into concrete life.
28) I am convinced that one must lift oneself into the ethereal realm of concepts if one wants to experience existence in all its aspects.
29) One who understands only the pleasures of the senses, misses the essential enjoyments of life.
30) Oriental sages have their students first spend years in renunciation and asceticism for years before they impart their own wisdom to them.
31) The Western world no longer requires devote exercises and ascetic practices as a preparation for science, but it does demand that one should have the good will to withdraw, for a brief time, from the immediate impressions of life and enter the realm of pure thought.
32) The fields of life are many, and for each of them special sciences develop.
33) But life itself is a whole, and the more the sciences strive to penetrate into the depths of the separate realms, the more they withdraw themselves from seeing the world as a living unity.
34) There must be a knowledge that seeks in the separate sciences, the principle that leads man back to the full life once more.
35) Through his knowledge a scientific specialist wants to become conscious of the world and how it works; in this book the aim is a philosophical one: science itself must become a living, organic entity.
36) The various branches of science are preludes to the science striven for here.
37) A similar relationship is to be found in art.
38) The composer’s work is based on the theory of composition, which is a sum of knowledge which is a necessary prerequisite for composing.
39) In composing, the law of composition serves life, serves the true reality.
40) In exactly the same way, philosophy is an art.
41) All real philosophers have truly been artists in concepts.
42) For them, human ideas become artistic materials , and the scientific method becomes artistic technique.
43) Thereby, abstract thinking gains concrete, individual life.
44) Ideas become life’s forces.
45) Then we have not just a knowledge of things, but we have lifted knowledge into a real organism, ruled by its own laws; our consciousness active and real has risen beyond a mere passive reception of truths.
46) How philosophy as an art is related to human freedom, what freedom is, and whether we do or can participate in it, is the principal theme of my book.
47) All other scientific discussions are included solely because they ultimately throw light on this question which, in my opinion, is man’s most immediate concern.
48) These pages are to offer a “Philosophy of Freedom.”
49) All science would be nothing but the satisfaction of idle curiosity if it were not aimed at heightening the value of existence of the human personality.
50) The sciences attain their true value only through presenting the significance of their results in relation to man.
51) The ultimate goal of the individual cannot be the ennoblement of only a single faculty of the soul, but a development of all the capacities that slumber within us.
52) Knowledge has value only like a contribution to the all-round development of human’s whole nature.
53) Therefore, in this book the relation between science and life is not regarded in the sense that man must bow down to ideas and dedicate their forces to its service; rather the relation should be that we can win the world of ideas in order to make use of it for our human goals, which go beyond the aims of mere science.
54) We need to put our self in front of the idea in a living experience; otherwise we can fall into its tyranny.

Rudolf Steiner

PREFACE TO THE REVISED EDITION, 1918

Everything discussed in this book centers around two root problems of the human soul.

The first is: can we understand human nature in such a way that this understanding serves as the basis for everything else we may meet through life experience or through science,

for we often feel the results of scientific investigations are not self-supporting,

because doubt and critical thinking can drive it into the realm of uncertainty?

The other question is: can man being, as willing entity, ascribe freedom to his

will, or

is freedom of will an illusion arising out of his inability to recognize the threads of necessity on which his will depends, just like a process in nature?

This is no artful structured question. In a certain disposition it arises quite spontaneously in the human soul.

And man could feel that the soul would be less than it should be if it has not at some time come face to face with these two possibilities: freedom or necessity of the will.

In this book the intention is to show that the inner experiences caused by the second problem depend upon what attitude man is able to take towards the first problem.

It is possible to attain such

a conception of man

’s nature, that can support

all

other knowledge, and further that this insight completely justifies the concept of freedom of will, provided that one finds the region of 

the soul where free will can develop.

Translation Italian graphic:

Two problems

The relation to the two problems is such that, once attained, it can become a living content of man’s soul life.

No theoretical answer is given. Once will is acquired, it is merely carried about as a conviction, retained by memory.

For the whole manner of thinking on which this book is based, such an answer would be an illusion.

Such a finished, limited answer is not provided here , but a region of experiences within the human soul will be pointed to, where, through the soul’s own inner activity, living answers to the questions are to be found ever anew and whenever a human being needs it.

Once the region of soul is discovered where these questions unfold, a real insight into this region provides man with what he needs for the solution of these two problems of life so that, with what he has then attained, he can penetrate further into the breadth and depth of life’s riddles, as need or destiny leads him.

It will be seen that a knowledge has here been outlined, which proves its justification and validity, not only through its own existence, but also through the relationship it has with the whole soul-life of man.

These were my thoughts about the content of this book when I wrote it out twenty-five years ago.

Today as well, I must characterize

the book’s

aim in the same way.

In the first edition I limited myself to saying no more than was in the strictest sense connected with the two root questions described above.

If anyone is surprised to find nothing in this book as yet, any reference to that region of the world of spiritual experience described in my later writings, then he must consider that at that time it was not my purpose to describe results of spiritual research, but first to lay the foundation on which such results can rest.

This “Philosophy of Freedom” does not contain any special results of that kind, any more than it contains special results of the natural sciences. But what it contains cannot, in my view, be dispensed by anyone who strives for certainty in such knowledge.

What I have said in this

book

might also be acceptable to many who, for reasons of their own, will have nothing to do with the results of my spiritual scientific research.

But anyone who can regard this research as something to which he is drawn, will recognize as important what is attempted here.

It is this: to prove that an open-minded consideration of just the two problems I have indicated, problems which are fundamental to all knowledge, leads to the view to recognise the fact that man is living within the reality of a spiritual world.

In this book the attempt is made to validate cognition of the spiritual realm before entering upon spiritual experience.

And this justification is undertaken in such a way that, for anyone able and willing to enter into this discussion, there is no need, in order to accept what is said here, to cast furtive glances at the experiences which my later writings have shown to be relevant.

Thus this book seems to me quite separate from my actual 

spiritual-scientific writings, on the other hand, it is also most intimately connected with them.

For this now, after twenty-five years, I can republish 

the text essentially unaltered.

I have, however, made additions of some length to several chapters.

Misinterpretations of what I had said made such detailed extensions seem necessary.

The only passages I have modified are those in which, a

quarter of a century ago, I had clumsily expressed. (Only ill

will could find in these changes occasion to suggest that I have changed my fundamental conviction.)

The book has now been out of print for many years.

Nevertheless, and in spite of the fact, apparent from what I have just said, I feel that the same things need to be said today as twenty-five 

years ago, I hesitated a long time about the completion of this revised edition.

Again and again I have asked myself whether at this point or that, I ought not to define my position toward the numerous philosophical views which have been put forward since the publication of the first edition.

Yet the heavy demands on my time in recent years, due to purely spiritual scientific research, prevented me doing as I might have wished.

A survey, as thorough as possible, of the philosophical literature of the present day has convinced me that such a critical discussion, tempting though it would be in itself, has no place in the context of what this book has to say.

All that, from the point of view of the “Philosophy of Freedom,” seemed necessary for me to say about recent philosophical tendencies, may be found in the second volume of my “Riddles of Philosophy.”

April 1918 RUDOLF STEINER

THE PHILOSOPHY OF FREEDOM

 

KNOWLEDGE OF FREEDOM

 

1

CONSCIOUS HUMAN ACTION

Is a human being in his thinking and acting a spiritually free being, or subject to the iron necessity of purely natural law?

Few questions have been debated with so much ingenuity more than this one.

The

idea of the freedom of the human will has found enthusiastic supporters and stubborn opponents in plenty.

There are those who, in moral zeal, declare it to be sheer stupidity to deny so evident a fact as freedom.

Opposed to them are others who regard as utterly naive the belief that the uniformity of natural law is interrupted in the sphere of human action and thinking.

The same thing is here declared as often to be the most precious possession of humankind, and as its worst illusion.

Infinite subtlety has been expended, to explain how human freedom is compatible with the working of nature, to which, after all, man belongs.

No less effort has been taken to make comprehensible, from the other side, how a delusion like this could have arisen.

That here we are dealing with one of the most important questions of life, religion, conduct and science, which is felt by everyone whose character is not totally devoid of depth.

And indeed, it belongs to the sad signs of the superficiality of present day thinking that a book which attempts to develop a “new belief” David Friedrich Strauss’s

The Old and New Belief

out of the results of the latest scientific discoveries, contains, on this question, nothing but the words:

“Here we must deal not with the problem of human will.

The supposed indifferent freedom of choice has always been recognized as an empty illusion by every philosophy worthy of the name. The moral valuation of human conduct and character remains untouched by this question.”

I mention this

passage, not because I consider that the book from which it derives

has

any special importance, but because it seems to me to express the only view which most of our thinking contemporaries are able to achieve on this question.

Nowadays everyone who claims to have advanced beyond a kindergarten education seems to know that freedom cannot consist in choosing

arbitrarily between two possible actions.

There is always a quite specific reason why, out of several possible actions, a person carries out a particular one.

This seems obvious.

However in present-day, by the opponents of freedom, the principal attacks are directed only against the freedom of choice.

Herbert Spencer, who has views which are gaining wider acceptance, says: “That anyone could desire or not desire arbitrarily,

which is the fundamental principle in the dogma of free will, is negated

through the analysis of consciousness, as well as by the contents of the preceding chapter.” [on psychology].

From the same point of view also

others, proceed

in combating the concept of free will.

In germ, all the considerations

can all be found as early as Spinoza

All that he brought forward with clarity and simplicity against the idea of freedom has since been repeated countless times, but usually veiled in the most complicated theoretical doctrines so that it is difficult to recognize the simple and direct course of thought on which all depends.

In a letter of October or November, 1674, Spinoza writes:

“I call free a thing which exists and acts out

of the

pure necessity of its nature, and I call it compelled, if the existence and action of which are exact and fixed manners determined by something else. The existence of God, for example, though necessity, is free because He exists only through the necessity of His nature. Similarly, God knows Himself and all else in freedom, because it follows solely from the necessity of His nature that He knows everything. You see, then, that I locate freedom, not in free decision, but in free necessity.

“But let us descend to created things which are all determined to exist and to act in a fixed and definite way by external causes. To look at this more clearly, let us imagine a very simple case. A stone, for example, receives a certain momentum from an external cause acting upon it, by which necessarily continues to move it after the impact of the external cause has ceased. The persistence of the stone is compelled,

not necessarily

, because it has to be defined by the thrust of the external cause. What applies here for the stone is fair also for everything else, however complicated and multifaceted it may be, namely, everything

is

necessarily determined by an outside cause to exist and to act in a fixed and precise manner.

“Now, please, assume that the stone during its motion, thinks and knows that it is striving as much as it can, to continue in motion. This stone which is conscious only of its

effort and

is by no means indifferent, will believe that it is

completely

free, and that it continues in motion for no other reason than its own will to continue. But this human freedom that we all claim to possess and that only consists

in people

being aware of their desires, but do not Know the causes by which they are determined.

So the child believes that

it freely

desires milk, the angry boy who is free in his demand for revenge, and the coward flight. Alike, the drunken man believes that he says of his own free decision what, sober again, he would wish that he had not said, and as this prejudice is innate in all

humans, it

is not easy to free oneself from it.

In fact, although experience shows

us often enough that man, least of all, can moderate his desires and that, moved by conflicting passions, he sees the better and pursues the worse, yet he considers himself free, simply because there are some things which he desires less intensely

and many desires which can easily be inhibited through the recollection of something else

that they think often

.”

Because this view is expressed so clearly and definitely, it is also easy to discover the fundamental error in it.

As a stone necessarily continues a definite movement after being put in motion, just as necessarily is a human being supposed to carry out an action if impelled to it by any reason.

Only because man is aware of his action, he imagines himself to be the free originator of his action. But, in so doing, he

overlooks the fact that he is driven by a cause which he has to obey unconditionally.

The error in this train of thought is easily found.

Spinoza, and all who think like him, overlook the fact that man not only is aware of his action, but also of the causes by which one’s actions are guided.

No one will deny that a child is

unfree

when it desires milk, as is also the drunken man who says things he later regrets.

Both know nothing of the causes working in the depths of their organisms, that exercise irresistible power over them.

But is it justifiable to lump together actions of this kind with those in which a man is conscious, not only of his actions but also of the reasons that motivate him?

Are the actions of human

beings really

all of one kind?

Should the deed of a warrior on the battlefield, of a scientist in his laboratory, of the statesman in complex negotiations, be placed, scientifically, on the same level as that of the child when it desires milk?

It is indeed true that the solution to a problem is best sought where it is simplest. But inability to differentiate has caused endless confusion before now.

After all, there is a profound difference

between

knowing and not knowing why I do something, or not.

At first sight this seems self-evident..

And yet the opponents of freedom never ask whether a motive that I recognize , and see through, compels me in the same sense as does the organic process that causes a child to cry for milk.

Eduard von Hartmann, in his

Phenomenology of Moral Consciousness

, page … maintains that the human will depends on two main factors: motive and character.

If one considers all men as alike, or at

least the

differences between them as negligible, then their will appears as determined from without, namely by the circumstances

of the outside world.

B

ut if we consider

that different men let a representation become a motive for their deeds only if their character is such that the particular representation arouses a desire in them, then man appears as determined from

within

and not from

without

.

Man believes himself to be free, that is, independent of external motives, in fact a representation pressing in on him from without must first be adopted as a motive, in accordance with his character.

The

truth, according

to Eduard von Hartmann, is that “even though we ourselves first turn a representation into a motive, yet we do so not arbitrarily, but according to the necessity of our characterological disposition

, that is, we are anything but free.”

(Rudolf Steiner inserts here the concept of "characterological disposition"which will resume in the ninth chapter..r.n.)

v.1- N.40

Translation Italian graphic:
motive,representations,characterological disposition.

Here again, is absolutely ignored the difference between motives that I allow to influence me only after I have permeated them with my consciousness, and those that I follow without having any clear knowledge of them.

This leads directly to the standpoint from which the matter will be considered here.

The question of the freedom of our will, can be posed by itself in isolation?

And if not: With what other question must it necessarily be linked?

If there is a difference between a conscious motive and an unconscious impulse, then the conscious motive will result in an action that must be judged differently from one done out of blind impulse.

The first question must concern this difference, and upon the answer will depend the position we must take on freedom itself.

What does it mean to have

knowledge

of the motives for one’s action?

Unfortunately

we5 always tear in two the inseparable whole: man.

In fact, this issue hasn’t been considered enough.

 

v.n.2

v.n.3

v.n.4

Translation Italian graphic: the knower, the doer, the knowingdoer(Rudolf Steiner inserts here the concept of "man who acts according to knowledge". r.n.) N.49

We distinguish the doer from the knower,

but we have neglected

the one who matters most : the man who acts out of knowledge.

It is said: Man is free when he

obeys reason

alone, not his animal desires.

Or else: Freedom means being able to determine one’s life and action according to purposes and deliberate decisions.

Nothing is gained by such assertions.

For the question is just whether reason, purposes and decisions exercise control over men in the same way as animal desires.

If a reasonable decision arises in me, without my

doing, with

just the same necessity as hunger and thirst, then our want must obey it, and my freedom is an illusion.

Another phrase is: To be free means not being able to will what one wants, but being able to do what one wills.

In his

Atomistics of the Will

, the poet-philosopher Robert Hamerling

expresses

this idea with great clearness : Man can certainly do what he wills, but he cannot will what he wants, since his will is determined by

motives.

He cannot

want what

he wills?

Let us consider these words more closely. Have they any sense?

Should freedom of will consist in being able to will something without ground, without a motive?

But what does it mean to will something, other than

having grounds

to

do or to strive for this rather than that?

To will something without reason, without motive, would mean to will something

without willing it

.

The concept of will is inseparably connected to the concept of motivation.

Without a determining motive, the will is an empty ability; active and real should become only through the motive.

It Is therefore absolutely

right that

the humans will is not “free”, in as much as its direction is always determined by the strongest motive.

But in contrast to this

unfreedom,

it is absurd, to speak of a thinkable ‘freedom’ of the will, that would consist in being able to will

what one does not will.

Robert Hamerling

Atomistik des Willens

(Volume 2, p. 213 ff.)

Here again, without considering the difference between conscious and unconscious motives, are discussed only motives in general.