The Principles of Psychology, Vol. II - William James - E-Book

The Principles of Psychology, Vol. II E-Book

William James

0,0
0,99 €

oder
-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

Experience the life-changing power of William James with this unforgettable book.

Das E-Book wird angeboten von und wurde mit folgenden Begriffen kategorisiert:

Das E-Book können Sie in Legimi-Apps oder einer beliebigen App lesen, die das folgende Format unterstützen:

EPUB
Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



The Principles of Psychology

Volume 2

by William James

CONTENTS.

CHAPTER XVII.

SENSATION

Its distinction from perception. Its cognitive

function--acquaintance with qualities. No pure sensations after the

first days of life. The 'relativity of knowledge'. The law of

contrast. The psychological and the physiological theories of it.

Hering's experiments. The 'eccentric projection' of sensations.

CHAPTER XVIII.

IMAGINATION

Our images are usually vague. Vague images not necessarily general

notions. Individuals differ in imagination; Gabon's researches.

The 'visile' type, 58. The 'audile' type. The 'motile' type.

Tactile images, 65. The neural process of imagination. Its

relations to that of sensation.

CHAPTER XIX.

THE PERCEPTION OF 'THINGS'

Perception and sensation. Perception is of definite and probable

things. Illusions;--of the first type;--of the second

type. The neural process in perception. 'Apperception'.

Is perception an unconscious inference? Hallucinations,

114. The neural process in hallucination. Binet's theory.

'Perception-time'.

CHAPTER XX.

THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE

The feeling of crude extensity. The perception of spatial order.

Space-'relations'. The meaning of localization. 'Local

signs'. The construction of 'real' space. The subdivision

of the original sense-spaces. The sensation of motion over

surfaces. The measurement of the sense-spaces by each other.

Their summation. Feelings of movement in joints. Feelings

of muscular contraction. Summary so far. How the blind

perceive space. Visual space. Helmholtz and Reid on the

test of a sensation. The theory of identical points. The

theory of projection. Ambiguity of retinal impressions;--of

eye-movements. The choice of the visual reality. Sensations

which we ignore. Sensations which seem suppressed. Discussion

of Wundt's and Helmholtz's reasons for denying that retinal sensations

are of extension. Summary. Historical remarks.

CHAPTER XXI.

THE PERCEPTION OF REALITY

Belief and its opposites. The various orders of reality.

'Practical' realities. The sense of our own bodily existence is

the nucleus of all reality. The paramount reality of sensations.

The influence of emotion and active impulse on belief. Belief

in theories. Doubt. Relations of belief and will.

CHAPTER XXII.

REASONING

'Recepts'. In reasoning, we pick out essential qualities.

What is meant by a mode of conceiving. What is involved in the

existence of general propositions. The two factors of reasoning.

Sagacity. The part played by association by similarity.

The intellectual contrast between brute and man: association by

similarity the fundamental human distinction. Different orders of

human genius.

CHAPTER XXIII.

THE PRODUCTION OF MOVEMENT

The diffusive wave. Every sensation produces reflex effects on the

whole organism.

CHAPTER XXIV.

INSTINCT

Its definition. Instincts not always blind or invariable.

Two principles of non-uniformity in instincts: 1) Their inhibition by

habits; 2) Their transitoriness. Man has more instincts than

any other mammal. Reflex impulses. Imitation. Emulation.

Pugnacity. Sympathy. The hunting instinct. Fear.

Acquisitiveness. Constructiveness. Play. Curiosity.

Sociability and shyness. Secretiveness. Cleanliness.

Shame. Love. Maternal love.

CHAPTER XXV.

THE EMOTIONS

Instinctive reaction and emotional expression shade imperceptibly into

each other. The expression of grief; of fear; of hatred.

Emotion is a consequence, not the cause, of the bodily expression.

Difficulty of testing this view. Objections to it discussed.

The subtler emotions, 468. No special brain-centres for emotion.

Emotional differences between individuals. The genesis of the

various emotions.

CHAPTER XXVI.

WILL

Voluntary movements: they presuppose a memory of involuntary movements.

Kinæsthetic impressions, 488. No need to assume feelings of

innervation. The 'mental cue' for a movement may be an image of

its visual or auditory effects as well as an image of the way it feels.

Ideo-motor action. Action after deliberation. Five types

of decision. The feeling of effort. Unhealthiness of will:

1) The explosive type; 2) The obstructed type. Pleasure

and pain are not the only springs of action. All consciousness

is impulsive. What we will depends on what idea dominates in

our mind. The idea's outward effects follow from the cerebral

machinery. Effort of attention to a naturally repugnant idea is

the essential feature of willing. The free-will controversy.

Psychology, as a science, can safely postulate determinism, even if

free-will be true. The education of the Will. Hypothetical

brain-schemes.

CHAPTER XXVII.

HYPNOTISM

Modes of operating and susceptibility. Theories about the hypnotic

state. The symptoms of the trance.

CHAPTER XXVIII.

NECESSARY TRUTHS AND THE EFFECTS OF EXPERIENCE

Programme of the chapter. Elementary feelings are innate.

The question refers to their combinations. What is meant by

'experience'. Spencer on ancestral experience. Two ways

in which new cerebral structure arises: the 'back-door' and the

'front-door' way. The genesis of the elementary mental categories.

The genesis of the natural sciences. Scientific conceptions

arise as accidental variations. The genesis of the pure sciences.

Series of evenly increasing terms. The principle of mediate

comparison. That of skipped intermediaries. Classification.

Predication. Formal logic. Mathematical propositions.

Arithmetic. Geometry. Our doctrine is the same as

Locke's. Relations of ideas _v._ couplings of things The

natural sciences are inward ideal schemes with which the order of

nature proves congruent. Metaphysical principles are properly only

postulates. Æsthetic and moral principles are quite incongruent

with the order of nature. Summary of what precedes. The

origin of instincts. Insufficiency of proof for the transmission

to the next generation of acquired habits. Weismann's views.

Conclusion.

INDEX.

PSYCHOLOGY.

CHAPTER XVII.

SENSATION.

After inner perception, outer perception! The next three chapters will

treat of the processes by which we cognize at all times the present

world of space and the material things which it contains. And first, of

the process called Sensation.

SENSATION AND PERCEPTION DISTINGUISHED.

_The words Sensation and Perception_ do not carry very definitely

discriminated meanings in popular speech, and in Psychology also their

meanings run into each other. Both of them name processes in which we

cognize an objective world; both (under normal conditions) need the

stimulation of incoming nerves ere they can occur; Perception always

involves Sensation as a portion of itself; and Sensation in turn never

takes place in adult life without Perception also being there. They are

therefore names for different cognitive _functions_, not for different

sorts of mental _fact_. The nearer the object cognized comes to being a

simple quality like 'hot,' 'cold,' 'red,' 'noise,' 'pain,' apprehended

irrelatively to other things, the more the state of mind approaches

pure sensation. The fuller of relations the object is, on the contrary;

the more it is something classed, located, measured, compared, assigned

to a function, etc., etc.; the more unreservedly do we call the state

of mind a perception, and the relatively smaller is the part in it

which sensation plays.

_Sensation, then, so long as we take the analytic point of view,

differs from Perception only in the extreme simplicity of its object or

content._[1] Its function is that of mere _acquaintance_ with a fact.

Perception's function, on the other hand, is knowledge _about_[2] a

fact; and this knowledge admits of numberless degrees of complication.

But in both sensation and perception we perceive the fact as an

_immediately present outward reality_, and this makes them differ from

'thought' and 'conception,' whose objects do not appear present in this

immediate physical way. _From the physiological_ _point of view both

sensations and perceptions differ from 'thoughts'_ (in the narrower

sense of the word) _in the fact that nerve-currents coming in from

the periphery are involved in their production. In perception these

nerve-currents arouse voluminous associative or reproductive processes

in the cortex; but when sensation occurs alone, or with a minimum of

perception, the accompanying reproductive processes are at a minimum

too._

I shall in this chapter discuss some general questions more especially

relative to Sensation. In a later chapter perception will take its

turn. I shall entirely pass by the classification and natural history

of our special 'sensations,' such matters finding their proper place,

and being sufficiently well treated, in all the physiological books.[3]

THE COGNITIVE FUNCTION OF SENSATION.

_A pure sensation is an abstraction;_ and when we adults talk of our

'sensations' we mean one of two things: either certain _objects_,

namely simple _qualities_ or _attributes_ like _hard, hot, pain;_ or

else those of our thoughts in which acquaintance with these objects

is least combined with knowledge about the relations of them to other

things. As we can only think or talk about the relations of objects

with which we have _acquaintance_ already, we are forced to postulate

a function in our thought whereby we first become aware of the _bare

immediate natures_ by which our several objects are distinguished.

This function is sensation. And just as logicians always point out

the distinction between substantive terms of discourse and relations

found to obtain between them, so psychologists, as a rule, are ready to

admit this function, of the vision of the terms or matters meant, as

something distinct from the knowledge about them and of their relations

_inter se_. Thought with the former function is sensational, with the

latter, intellectual. Our earliest thoughts are almost exclusively

sensational. They merely give us a set of _thats_, or _its_, of

subjects of discourse, with their relations not brought out. The

first time we see _light_, in Condillac's phrase we _are_ it rather

rather than see it. But all our later optical knowledge is about what

this experience gives. And though we were struck blind from that first

moment, our scholarship in the subject would lack no essential feature

so long as our memory remained. In training-institutions for the blind

they teach the pupils as much _about_ light as in ordinary schools.

Reflection, refraction, the spectrum, the ether-theory, etc., are all

studied. But the best taught born-blind pupil of such an establishment

yet lacks a knowledge which the least instructed seeing baby has. They

can never show him what light is in its 'first intention'; and the loss

of that sensible knowledge no book-learning can replace. All this is so

obvious that we usually find sensation 'postulated' as an element of

experience, even by those philosophers who are least inclined to make

much of its importance, or to pay respect to the knowledge which it

brings.[4]

But the trouble is that most, if not all, of those who admit it,

admit it as a fractional _part_ of the thought, in the old-fashioned

atomistic sense which we have so often criticised.

Take the pain called toothache for example. Again and again we feel it

and greet it as the same real item in the universe. We must therefore,

it is supposed, have a distinct pocket for it in our mind into which it

and nothing else will fit. This pocket, when filled, is the sensation

of toothache; and must be either filled or half-filled whenever and

under whatever form toothache is present to our thought, and whether

much or little of the rest of the mind be filled at the same time.

Thereupon of course comes up the paradox and mystery: If the knowledge

of toothache be pent up in this separate mental pocket, how can it be

known _cum alio_ or brought into one view with anything else? This

pocket knows nothing else; no other part of the mind knows toothache.

The knowing of toothache _cum alio_ must be a miracle. And the miracle

must have an Agent. And the Agent must be a Subject or Ego 'out of

time,'--and all the rest of it, as we saw in Chapter X. And then begins

the well-worn round of recrimination between the sensationalists and

the spiritualists, from which we are saved by our determination from

the outset to accept the psychological point of view, and to admit

knowledge whether of simple toothaches or of philosophic systems as

an ultimate fact. There are realities and there are 'states of mind,'

and the latter know the former; and it is just as wonderful for a

state of mind to be a 'sensation' and know a simple pain as for it to

be a thought and know a system of related things.[5] But there is no

reason to suppose that when different states of mind know different

things about the same toothache, they do so by virtue of their all

_containing_ faintly or vividly the original pain. Quite the reverse.

The by-gone sensation of my gout was painful, as Reid somewhere says;

the _thought_ of the same gout as by-gone is pleasant, and in no

respect resembles the earlier mental state.

Sensations, then, first make us acquainted with innumerable things, and

then are replaced by thoughts which know the same things in altogether

other ways. And Locke's main doctrine remains eternally true, however

hazy some of his language may have been, that

 "though there be a great number of considerations wherein things

 may be compared one with another, and so a multitude of relations;

 yet they all _terminate in_, and are concerned about, those simple

 ideas[6] either of sensation or reflection, which I think to be the

 whole materials of all our knowledge.... The simple ideas we receive

 from sensation and reflection are the _boundaries_ of our thoughts;

 beyond which, the mind whatever efforts it would make, is not able to

 advance one jot; nor can it make any discoveries when it would pry

 into the nature and hidden causes of those ideas."[7]

The nature and hidden causes of ideas will never be unravelled till

the _nexus_ between the brain and consciousness is cleared up. All

we can say now is that sensations are _first_ things in the way of

consciousness. Before conceptions can come, sensations must have

come; but before sensations come, no psychic fact need have existed,

a nerve-current is enough. If the nerve-current be not given, nothing

else will take its place. To quote the good Locke again:

 "It is not in the power of the most exalted wit or enlarged

 understanding, by any quickness or variety of thoughts, to invent or

 frame one new simple idea [i.e. sensation] in the mind.... I would

 have any one try to fancy any taste which had never affected his

 palate, or frame the idea of a scent he had never smelt; and when

 he can do this, I will also conclude that a blind man hath ideas of

 colors, and a deaf man true distinct notions of sounds."[8]

The brain is so made that all currents in it run one way. Consciousness

of some sort goes with all the currents, but it is only when new

currents are entering that it has the sensational _tang_. And it is

only then that consciousness directly _encounters_ (to use a word of

Mr. Bradley's) a reality outside itself.

The difference between such encounter and all conceptual knowledge is

very great. A blind man may know all _about_ the sky's blueness, and

I may know all _about_ your toothache, conceptually; tracing their

causes from primeval chaos, and their consequences to the crack of

doom. But so long as he has not felt the blueness, nor I the toothache,

our knowledge, wide as it is, of these realities, will be hollow

and inadequate. Somebody must _feel_ blueness, somebody must _have_

toothache, to make human knowledge of these matters real. Conceptual

systems which neither began nor left off in sensations would be like

bridges without piers. Systems about fact must plunge themselves into

sensation as bridges plunge their piers into the rock. Sensations are

the stable rock, the _terminus a quo_ and the _terminus ad quem_ of

thought. To find such termini is our aim with all our theories--to

conceive first when and where a certain sensation may be had, and then

to have it. Finding it stops discussion. Failure to find it kills the

false conceit of knowledge. Only when you deduce a possible sensation

for me from your theory, and give it to me when and where the theory

requires, do I begin to be sure that your thought has anything to do

with truth.

_Pure sensations can only be realized in the earliest days of life._

They are all but impossible to adults with memories and stores of

associations acquired. Prior to all impressions on sense-organs the

brain is plunged in deep sleep and consciousness is practically

non-existent. Even the first weeks after birth are passed in almost

unbroken sleep by human infants. It takes a strong message from the

sense-organs to break this slumber. In a new-born brain this gives

rise to an absolutely pure sensation. But the experience leaves its

'unimaginable touch' on the matter of the convolutions, and the next

impression which a sense-organ transmits produces a cerebral reaction

in which the awakened vestige of the last impression plays its part.

Another sort of feeling and a higher grade of cognition are the

consequence; and the complication goes on increasing till the end of

life, no two successive impressions falling on an identical brain, and

no two successive thoughts being exactly the same. (See Vol. I, p. 230

ff.)

_The first sensation which an infant gets is for him the Universe._

And the Universe which he later comes to know is nothing but an

amplification and an implication of that first simple germ which,

by accretion on the one hand and intussusception on the other,

has grown so big and complex and articulate that its first estate

is unrememberable. In his dumb awakening to the consciousness of

_something there_, a mere _this_ as yet (or something for which

even the term _this_ would perhaps be too discriminative, and the

intellectual acknowledgment of which would be better expressed by

the bare interjection 'lo!'), the infant encounters an object in

which (though it be given in a pure sensation) all the 'categories

of the understanding' are contained. _It has objectivity, unity,

substantiality, causality, in the full sense in which any later object

or system of objects has these things._ Here the young knower meets

and greets his world; and the miracle of knowledge bursts forth, as

Voltaire says, as much in the infant's lowest sensation as in the

highest achievement of a Newton's brain. The physiological condition

of this first sensible experience is probably nerve-currents coming

in from many peripheral organs at once. Later, the one confused Fact

which these currents cause to appear is perceived to be many facts,

and to contain many qualities.[9] For as the currents vary, and the

brain-paths are moulded by them, other thoughts with other 'objects'

come, and the 'same thing' which was apprehended as a present _this_

soon figures as a past _that_, about which many unsuspected things have

come to light. The principles of this development have been laid down

already in Chapters XII and XIII, and nothing more need here be added

to that account.

"THE RELATIVITY OF KNOWLEDGE."

To the reader who is tired of so much _Erkenntnisstheorie_ I can only

say that I am so myself, but that it is indispensable, in the actual

state of opinions about Sensation, to try to clear up just what the

word means. Locke's pupils seek to do the impossible with sensations,

and against them we must once again insist that sensations 'clustered

together' cannot build up our more intellectual states of mind. Plato's

earlier pupils used to admit Sensation's existence, grudgingly, but

they trampled it in the dust as something corporeal, non-cognitive,

and vile.[10] His latest followers seem to seek to crowd it out of

existence altogether. The only reals for the neo-Hegelian writers

appear to be _relations_, relations without terms, or whose terms

are only speciously such and really consist in knots, or gnarls of

relations finer still _in infinitum_.

 "Exclude from what we have considered real all qualities constituted

 by relation, we find that none are left." "Abstract the many relations

 from the one thing and there is nothing.... Without the relations it

 would not exist at all."[11] "The single feeling is nothing real."

 "On the recognition of relations as constituting the _nature_ of

 ideas, rests the possibility of any tenable theory of their reality."

Such quotations as these from the late T. H. Green[12] would be matters

of curiosity rather than of importance, were it not that sensationalist

writers themselves believe in a so-called 'Relativity of Knowledge,'

which, if they only understood it, they would see to be identical

with Professor Green's doctrine. They tell us that the relation of

sensations to each other is something belonging to their essence, and

that no one of them has an absolute content:

 "That, e.g., black can only be felt in contrast to white, or at

 least in distinction from a paler or a deeper black; similarly a

 tone or a sound only in alternation with others or with silence; and

 in like manner a smell, a taste, a touch, only, so to speak, _in

 statu nascendi_, whilst, when the stimulus continues, all sensation

 disappears. This all seems at first sight to be splendidly consistent

 both with itself and with the facts. But looked at more closely, it is

 seen that neither is the case."[13]

The two leading facts from which the doctrine of universal relativity

derives its wide-spread credit are these:

1) The _psychological fact_ that so much of our actual knowledge _is_

of the relations of things--even our simplest sensations in adult life

are habitually referred to classes as we take them in; and

2) The _physiological fact_ that our senses and brain must have periods

of change and repose, else we cease to feel and think.

Neither of these facts proves anything about the presence or

non-presence to our mind of absolute qualities with which we become

sensibly acquainted. Surely not the psychological fact; for our

inveterate love of relating and comparing things does not alter the

intrinsic qualities or nature of the things compared, or undo their

absolute givenness. And surely not the physiological fact; for the

length of time during which we can feel or attend to a quality is

altogether irrelevant to the intrinsic constitution of the quality

felt. The time, moreover, is long enough in many instances, as

sufferers from neuralgia know.[14] And the doctrine of relativity,

not proved by these facts, is flatly disproved by other facts even

more patent. So far are we from not knowing (in the words of Professor

Bain) "any one thing by itself, but only the difference between it

and another thing," that if this were true the whole edifice of our

knowledge would collapse. If all we felt were the _difference_ between

the _C_ and _D_, or _c_ and _d_, on the musical scale, that being the

same in the two pairs of notes, the pairs themselves would be the same,

and language could get along without substantives. But Professor Bain

does not mean seriously what he says, and we need spend no more time on

this vague and popular form of the doctrine.[15] The facts which seem

to hover before the minds of its champions are those which are best

described under the head of a physiological law.

THE LAW OF CONTRAST.

I will first enumerate the main facts which fall under this law, and

then remark upon what seems to me their significance for psychology.[16]

[Nowhere are the phenomena of contrast better exhibited, and their

laws more open to accurate study, than in connection with the sense

of sight. Here both kinds--simultaneous and successive--can easily be

observed, for they are of constant occurrence. Ordinarily they remain

unnoticed, in accordance with the general law of economy which causes

us to select for conscious notice only such elements of our object as

will serve us for æsthetic or practical utility, and to neglect the

rest; just as we ignore the double images, the _mouches volantes_,

etc., which exist for everyone, but which are not discriminated

without careful attention. But by attention we may easily discover

the general facts involved in contrast. We find that _in general the

color and brightness of one object always apparently affect the color

and brightness of any other object seen simultaneously with it or

immediately after_.

In the first place, if we look for a moment at any surface and then

turn our eyes elsewhere, the complementary color and opposite degree

of brightness to that of the first surface tend to mingle themselves

with the color and the brightness of the second. This is _successive

contrast_. It finds its explanation in the fatigue of the organ of

sight, causing it to respond to any particular stimulus less and

less readily the longer such stimulus continues to act. This is

shown clearly in the very marked changes which occur in case of

continued fixation of one particular point of any field. The field

darkens slowly, becomes more and more indistinct, and finally, if

one is practised enough in holding the eye perfectly steady, slight

differences in shade and color may entirely disappear. If we now turn

aside the eyes, a negative after-image of the field just fixated at

once forms, and mingles its sensations with those which may happen to

come from anything else looked at. This influence is distinctly evident

only when the first surface has been 'fixated' without movement of

the eyes. It is, however, none the less present at all times, even

when the eye wanders from point to point, causing each sensation to

be modified more or less by that just previously experienced. On this

account successive contrast is almost sure to be present in cases of

simultaneous contrast, and to complicate the phenomena.

A _visual image is modified not only by other sensations just

previously experienced, but also by all those experienced

simultaneously with it, and especially by such as proceed from

contiguous portions of the retina_. This is the phenomenon of

_simultaneous contrast_. In this, as in successive contrast, both

brightness and hue are involved. A bright object appears still brighter

when its surroundings are darker than itself, and darker when they are

brighter than itself. Two colors side by side are apparently changed by

the admixture, with each, of the complement of the other. And lastly,

a gray surface near a colored one is tinged with the complement of the

latter.[17]

The phenomena of simultaneous contrast in sight are so complicated

by other attendant phenomena that it is difficult to isolate

them and observe them in their purity. Yet it is evidently of the

greatest importance to do so, if one would conduct his investigations

accurately. Neglect of this principle has led to many mistakes being

made in accounting for the facts observed. As we have seen, if the eye

is allowed to wander here and there about the field as it ordinarily

does, successive contrast results and allowance must be made for

its presence. It can be avoided only by carefully fixating with the

well-rested eye a point of one field, and by then observing the changes

which occur in this field when the contrasting field is placed by its

side. Such a course will insure pure simultaneous contrast. But even

thus it lasts in its purity for a moment only. It reaches its maximum

of effect immediately after the introduction of the contrasting field,

and then, if the fixation is continued, it begins to weaken rapidly

and soon disappears; thus undergoing changes similar to those observed

when any field whatever is fixated steadily and the retina becomes

fatigued by unchanging stimuli. If one continues still further to

fixate the same point, the color and brightness of one field tend to

spread themselves over and mingle with the color and brightness of the

neighboring fields, thus substituting '_simultaneous induction_' for

simultaneous contrast.

Not only must we recognize and eliminate the effects of successive

contrast, of temporal changes due to fixation, and of simultaneous

induction, in analyzing the phenomena of simultaneous contrast, but we

must also take into account _various other influences which modify its

effects_. Under favorable circumstances the contrast-effects are very

striking, and did they always occur as strongly they could not fail to

attract the attention. But they are not always clearly apparent, owing

to various disturbing causes which form no exception to the laws of

contrast, but which have a modifying effect on its phenomena. When,

for instance, the ground observed has many distinguishable features--a

_coarse grain, rough surface, intricate pattern,_ etc.--the contrast

effect appears weaker. This does not imply that the effects of contrast

are absent, but merely that the resulting sensations are overpowered

by the many other stronger sensations which entirely occupy the

attention. On such a ground a faint negative after-image--undoubtedly

due to retinal modifications--may become invisible; and even weak

objective differences in color may become imperceptible. For example, a

faint spot or grease-stain on woollen cloth, easily seen at a distance,

when the fibres are not distinguishable, disappears when closer

examination reveals the intricate nature of the surface.

Another frequent cause of the apparent absence of contrast is the

presence of narrow dark intermediate fields, such as are formed by

_bordering a field with black lines, or by the shaded contours of

objects_. When such fields interfere with the contrast, it is because

black and white can absorb much color without themselves becoming

clearly colored; and because such lines separate other fields too far

for them to distinctly influence one another. Even weak objective

differences in color may be made imperceptible by such means.

A third case where contrast does not clearly appear is where the _color

of the contrasting fields is too weak or too intense_, or where there

is _much difference in brightness between the two fields_. In the

latter case, as can easily be shown, it is the contrast of brightness

which interferes with the color-contrast and makes it imperceptible.

For this reason contrast shows best between fields of about equal

brightness. But the intensity of the color must not be too great, for

then its very darkness necessitates a dark contrasting field which

is too absorbent of induced color to allow the contrast to appear

strongly. The case is similar if the fields are too light.

_To obtain the best contrast-effects, therefore, the contracting fields

should be near together, should not be separated by shadows or black

lines, should be of homogeneous texture, and should be of about equal

brightness and medium intensity of color._ Such conditions do not

often occur naturally, the disturbing influences being present in case

of almost all ordinary objects, thus making the effects of contrast

far less evident. To eliminate these disturbances and to produce the

conditions most favorable for the appearance of good contrast-effects,

various experiments have been devised, which will be explained in

comparing the rival theories of explanation.

       *       *       *       *       *

There are _two theories--the psychological and the

physiological_--which attempt to explain the phenomena of contrast.

Of these the _psychological one_ was the first to gain prominence.

_Its most able advocate has been Helmholtz. It explains contrast

as a_ DECEPTION OF JUDGMENT. In ordinary life our sensations have

interest for us only so far as they give us practical knowledge.

Our chief concern is to recognize objects, and we have no occasion

to estimate exactly their absolute brightness and color. Hence we

gain no facility in so doing, but neglect the constant changes in

their shade, and are very uncertain as to the exact degree of their

brightness or tone of their color. When objects are near one another

"we are inclined to consider those differences which are clearly and

surely perceived as greater than those which appear uncertain in

perception or which must be judged by aid of memory,"[18] just as we

see a medium-sized man taller than he really is when he stands beside

a short man. Such deceptions are more easily possible in the judgment

of small differences than of large ones; also where there is but one

element of difference instead of many. In a large number of cases of

contrast, in all of which a whitish spot is surrounded on all sides

by a colored surface--Meyer's experiment, the mirror experiment,

colored shadows, etc., soon to be described--the contrast is produced,

according to Helmholtz, by the fact that "a colored illumination or a

transparent colored covering appears to be spread out over the field,

and observation does not show directly that it fails on the white

spot."[19] We therefore believe that we see the latter through the

former color. Now

 "Colors have their greatest importance for us in so far as they are

 properties of bodies and can serve as signs for the recognition

 of bodies.... We have become accustomed, in forming a judgment in

 regard to the colors of bodies, to eliminate the varying brightness

 and color of the illumination. We have sufficient opportunity to

 investigate the same colors of objects in full sunshine, in the blue

 light of the clear sky, in the weak white light of a cloudy day, in

 the reddish-yellow light of the sinking sun or of the candle. Moreover

 the colored reflections of surrounding objects are involved. Since

 we see the same colored objects under these varying illuminations,

 we learn to form a correct conception of the color of the object in

 spite of the difference in illumination, i.e. to judge how such an

 object would appear in white illumination; and since only the constant

 color of the object interests us, we do not become conscious of the

 particular sensations on which our judgment rests. So also we are

 at no loss, when we see an object through a colored covering, to

 distinguish what belongs to the color of the covering and what to

 the object. In the experiments mentioned we do the same also where

 the covering over the object is not at all colored, because of the

 deception into which we fall, and in consequence of which we ascribe

 to the body a false color, the color complementary to the colored

 portion of the covering."[20]

We think that we see the complementary color through the colored

covering,--for these two colors together would give the sensation of

white which is actually experienced. If, however, in any way the white

spot is recognized as an independent object, or if it is compared with

another object known to be white, our judgment is no longer deceived

and the contrast does not appear.

 "As soon as the contrasting field is recognized as an independent

 body which lies above the colored ground, or even through an adequate

 tracing of its outlines is seen to be a separate field, the contrast

 disappears. Since, then, the judgment of the spatial position, the

 material independence, of the object in question is decisive for the

 determination of its color, it follows that the contrast-color arises

 not through an act of sensation but through an act of judgment."[21]

In short, the apparent change in color or brightness through contrast

is due to no change in excitation of the organ, to no change in

sensation; but in consequence of a false judgment the unchanged

sensation is wrongly interpreted, and thus leads to a changed

_perception_ of the brightness or color.

       *       *       *       *       *

In opposition to this theory has been developed one which attempts to

explain all cases of contrast as depending purely on _physiological

action of the terminal apparatus of vision. Hering is the most

prominent supporter of this view._ By great originality in devising

experiments and by insisting on rigid care in conducting them, he has

been able to detect the faults in the psychological theory and to

practically establish the validity of his own. Every visual sensation,

he maintains, is correlated to a physical process in the nervous

apparatus. Contrast is occasioned, not by a false idea resulting from

unconscious conclusions, but by the fact that the excitation of any

portion of the retina--and the consequent sensation--depends not only

on its own illumination, but on that of the rest of the retina as well.

 "If this psycho-physical process is aroused, as usually happens, by

 light-rays impinging on the retina, its nature depends not only on

 the nature of these rays, but also on the constitution of the entire

 nervous apparatus which is connected with the organ of vision, and on

 the state in which it finds itself."[22]

When a limited portion of the retina is aroused by external stimuli,

the rest of the retina, and especially the immediately contiguous

parts, tends to react also, and in such a way as to produce

therefrom the sensation of the opposite degree of brightness and the

complementary color to that of the directly-excited portion. When a

gray spot is seen alone, and again when it appears colored through

contrast, the objective light from the spot is in both cases the same.

Helmholtz maintains that the neural process and the corresponding

_sensation_ also remain unchanged, but are differently _interpreted_;

Hering, that the neural process and the sensation are themselves

changed, and that the 'interpretation' is the direct conscious

correlate of the altered retinal conditions. According to the one, the

contrast is psychological in its origin; according to the other, it is

purely physiological. In the cases cited above where the contrast-color

is no longer apparent--on a ground with many distinguishable features,

on a field whose borders are traced with black lines, etc.,--the

psychological theory, as we have seen, attributes this to the fact

that under these circumstances we judge the smaller patch of color to

be an independent object on the surface, and are no longer deceived

in judging it to be something over which the color of the ground is

drawn. The physiological theory, on the other hand, maintains that the

contrast-effect is still produced, but that the conditions are such

that the slight changes in color and brightness which it occasions

become imperceptible.

       *       *       *       *       *

The two theories, stated thus broadly, may seem equally plausible.

Hering, however, has conclusively proved, by experiments with

after-images, that the process on one part of the retina does modify

that on neighboring portions, under conditions where deception of

judgment is impossible.[23] A careful examination of the facts of

contrast will show that its phenomena must be due to this cause. _In

all the cases which one may investigate it will be seen that the

upholders of the psychological theory have failed to conduct their

experiments with sufficient care._ They have not excluded successive

contrast, have overlooked the changes due to steady fixation, and have

failed to properly account for the various modifying influences which

have been mentioned above. We can easily establish this if we examine

the most striking experiments in simultaneous contrast.

Of these one of the best known and most easily arranged is that known

as _Meyer's experiment_. A scrap of gray paper is placed on a colored

background, and both are covered by a sheet of transparent white paper.

The gray spot then assumes a contrast-color, complementary to that of

the background, which shines with a whitish tinge through the paper

which covers it. Helmholtz explains the phenomenon thus:

 "If the background is green, the covering-paper itself appears to be

 of a greenish color. If now the substance of the paper extends without

 apparent interruption over the gray which lies under it, we think that

 we see an object glimmering through the greenish paper, and such an

 object must in turn be rose-red, in order to give white light. If,

 however, the gray spot has its limits so fixed that it appears to be

 an independent object, the continuity with the greenish portion of the

 surface fails, and we regard it as a gray object which lies on this

 surface."[24]

The contrast-color may thus be made to disappear by tracing in black

the outlines of the gray scrap, or by placing above the tissue paper

another gray scrap of the same degree of brightness, and comparing

together the two grays. On neither of them does the contrast-color now

appear.

Hering[25] shows clearly that this interpretation is incorrect, and

that the disturbing factors are to be otherwise explained. In the first

place, the experiment can be so arranged that we could not possibly be

deceived into believing that we see the gray through a colored medium.

Out of a sheet of gray paper cut strips 5 mm. wide in such a way that

there will be alternately an empty space and a bar of gray, both of the

same width, the bars being held together by the uncut edges of the gray

sheet (thus presenting an appearance like a gridiron). Lay this on a

colored background--e.g. green--cover both with transparent paper, and

above all put a black frame which covers all the edges, leaving visible

only the bars, which are now alternately green and gray. The gray bars

appear strongly colored by contrast, although, since they occupy as

much space as the green bars, we are not deceived into believing that

we see the former through a green medium. The same is true if we weave

together into a basket pattern narrow strips of green and gray and

cover them with the transparent paper.

Why, then, if it is a true sensation due to physiological causes, and

not an error of judgment, which causes the contrast, does the color

disappear when the outlines of the gray scrap are traced, enabling us

to recognize it as an independent object? In the first place, it does

not necessarily do so, as will easily be seen if the experiment is

tried. The contrast-color often remains distinctly visible in spite

of the black outlines. In the second place, there are many adequate

reasons why the effect should be modified. Simultaneous contrast is

always strongest at the border-line of the two fields; but a narrow

black field now separates the two, and itself by contrast strengthens

the whiteness of both original fields, which were already little

saturated in color; and on black and on white, contrast-colors show

only under the most favorable circumstances. Even weak objective

differences in color may be made to disappear by such tracing of

outlines, as can be seen if we place on a gray background a scrap of

faintly-colored paper, cover it with transparent paper and trace its

outlines. Thus we see that it is not the recognition of the contrasting

field as an independent object which interferes with its color, but

rather a number of entirely explicable physiological disturbances.

The same may be proved in the case of holding above the tissue paper a

second gray scrap and comparing it with that underneath. To avoid the

disturbances caused by using papers of different brightness, the second

scrap should be made exactly like the first by covering the same gray

with the same tissue paper, and carefully cutting a piece about 10 mm.

square out of both together. To thoroughly guard against successive

contrast, which so easily complicates the phenomena, we must carefully

prevent all previous excitation of the retina by colored light. This

may be done by arranging thus: Place the sheet of tissue paper on a

glass pane, which rests on four supports; under the paper put the first

gray scrap. By means of a wire, fasten the second gray scrap 2 or 3 cm.

above the glass plate. Both scraps appear exactly alike, except at the

edges. Gaze now at both scraps, with eyes not exactly accommodated, so

that they appear near one another, with a very narrow space between.

Shove now a colored field (green) underneath the glass plate, and the

contrast appears at once on both scraps. If it appears less clearly

on the upper scrap, it is because of its bright and dark edges, its

inequalities, its grain, etc. When the accommodation is exact, there is

no essential change, although then on the upper scrap the bright edge

on the side toward the light, and the dark edge on the shadow side,

disturb somewhat. By continued fixation the contrast becomes weaker

and finally yields to simultaneous induction, causing the scraps to

become indistinguishable from the ground. Remove the green field and

both scraps become green, by successive induction. If the eye moves

about freely these last-named phenomena do not appear, but the contrast

continues indefinitely and becomes stronger. When Helmholtz found that

the contrast on the lower scrap disappeared, it was evidently because

he then really held the eye fixed. This experiment may be disturbed by

holding the upper scrap wrongly and by the differences in brightness of

its edges, or by other inequalities, but not by that recognizing of it

'as an independent body lying above the colored ground,' on which the

psychological explanation rests.

In like manner the claims of the psychological explanation can be

shown to be inadequate in other cases of contrast. Of frequent use

are revolving disks, which are especially efficient in showing good

contrast-phenomena, because all inequalities of the ground disappear

and leave a perfectly homogeneous surface. On a white disk are arranged

colored sectors, which are interrupted midway by narrow black fields in

such a way that when the disk is revolved the white becomes mixed with

the color and the black, forming a colored disk of weak saturation on

which appears a gray ring. The latter is colored by contrast with the

field which surrounds it. Helmholtz explains the fact thus:

 "The difference of the compared colors appears greater than it really

 is either because this difference, when it is the only existing one

 and draws the attention to itself alone, makes a stronger impression

 than when it is one among many, or because the different colors of the

 surface are conceived as alterations of the one ground-color of the

 surface such as might arise through shadows falling on it, through

 colored reflexes, or through mixture with colored paint or dust. In

 truth, to produce an objectively gray spot on a green surface, a

 reddish coloring would be necessary."[26]

This explanation is easily proved false by painting the disk with

narrow green and gray concentric rings, and giving each a different

saturation. The contrast appears though there is no ground-color, and

no longer a single difference, but many. The facts which Helmholtz

brings forward in support of his theory are also easily turned against

him. He asserts that if the color of the ground is too intense, or

if the gray ring is bordered by black circles, the contrast becomes

weaker; that no contrast appears on a white scrap held over the

colored field; and that the gray ring when compared with such scrap

loses its contrast-color either wholly or in part. Hering points out

the inaccuracy of all these claims. Under favorable conditions it is

impossible to make the contrast disappear by means of black enclosing

lines, although they naturally form a disturbing element; increase

in the saturation of the field, if disturbance through increasing

brightness-contrast is to be avoided, demands a darker gray field, on

which contrast-colors are less easily perceived; and careful use of the

white scrap leads to entirely different results. The contrast-color

does appear upon it when it is first placed above the colored field;

but if it is carefully fixated, the contrast-color diminishes very

rapidly both on it and on the ring, from causes already explained.

To secure accurate observation, all complication through successive

contrast should be avoided thus: first arrange the white scrap, then

interpose a gray screen between it and the disk, rest the eye, set the

wheel in motion, fixate the scrap, and then have the screen removed.

The contrast at once appears clearly, and its disappearance through

continued fixation can be accurately watched.

Brief mention of a few other cases of contrast must suffice. The

so-called mirror experiment consists of placing at an angle of 45º a

green (or otherwise colored) pane of glass, forming an angle with two

white surfaces, one horizontal and the other vertical. On each white

surface is a black spot. The one on the horizontal surface is seen

through the glass and appears dark green, the other is reflected from

the surface of the glass to the eye, and appears by contrast red. The

experiment may be so arranged that we are not aware of the presence of

the green glass, but think that we are looking directly at a surface

with green and red spots upon it; in such a case there is no deception

of judgment caused by making allowance for the colored medium through

which we think that we see the spot, and therefore the psychological

explanation does not apply. On excluding successive contrast by

fixation the contrast soon disappears as in all similar experiments.[27]

_Colored shadows_ have long been thought to afford a convincing proof

of the fact that simultaneous contrast is psychological in its origin.

They are formed whenever an opaque object is illuminated from two

separate sides by lights of different colors. When the light from one

source is white, its shadow is of the color of the other light, and

the second shadow is of a color complementary to that of the field

illuminated by both lights. If now we take a tube, blackened inside,

and through it look at the colored shadow, none of the surrounding

field being visible, and then have the colored light removed, the

shadow still appears colored, although 'the circumstances which

caused it have disappeared.' This is regarded by the psychologists as

conclusive evidence that the color is due to deception of judgment.

It can, however, easily be shown that the persistence of the color

seen through the tube is due to fatigue of the retina through the

prevailing light, and that when the colored light is removed the color

slowly disappears as the equilibrium of the retina becomes gradually

restored. When successive contrast is carefully guarded against, the

simultaneous contrast, whether seen directly or through the tube, never

lasts for an instant on removal of the colored field. The physiological

explanation applies throughout to all the phenomena presented by

colored shadows.[28]

If we have a small field whose illumination remains constant,

surrounded by a large field of changing brightness, an increase or

decrease in brightness of the latter results in a corresponding

apparent decrease or increase respectively in the brightness of the

former, while the large field seems to be unchanged. Exner says:

 "This illusion of sense shows that we are inclined to regard as

 constant the dominant brightness in our field of vision, and hence to

 refer the changing difference between this and the brightness of a

 limited field to a change in brightness of the latter."

The result, however, can be shown to depend not on illusion, but on

actual retinal changes, which alter the sensation experienced. The

irritability of those portions of the retina lighted by the large field

becomes much reduced in consequence of fatigue, so that the increase

in brightness becomes much less apparent than it would be without this

diminution in irritability. The small field, however, shows the change

by a change in the contrast-effect induced upon it by the surrounding

parts of the retina.[29]

The above cases show clearly that _physiological processes, and not

deception of judgment, are responsible for contrast of color_. To say

this, however, is not to maintain that our perception of a color is

never in any degree modified by our judgment of what the particular

colored thing before us may be. We have unquestionable illusions of

color due to wrong inferences as to what object is before us. Thus Von

Kries[30] speaks of wandering through evergreen forests covered with

snow, and thinking that through the interstices of the boughs he saw

the deep blue of pine-clad mountains, covered with snow and lighted by

brilliant sunshine; whereas what he really saw was the white snow on

trees near by, lying in shadow].[31]

Such a mistake as this is undoubtedly of psychological origin. It is

a wrong _classification_ of the appearances, due to the arousal of

intricate processes of association amongst which is the suggestion of a

different hue from that really before the eyes. In the ensuing chapters

such illusions as this will be treated of in considerable detail. But

it is a mistake to interpret the simpler cases of contrast in the light

of such illusions as these. These illusions can be rectified in an

instant, and we then wonder how they could have been. They come from

insufficient attention, or from the fact that the impression which we

get is a sign of more than one possible object, and can be interpreted

in either way. In none of these points do they resemble simple

color-contrast, which _unquestionably is a phenomenon of sensation

immediately aroused_.

       *       *       *       *       *

I have dwelt upon the facts of color-contrast at such great length

because they form so good a text to comment on in my struggle

against the view that sensations are immutable psychic things which

coexist with higher mental functions. Both sensationalists and

intellectualists agree that such sensations exist. They _fuse_, say

the pure sensationalists, and _make_ the higher mental function;

they _are combined_ by activity of the Thinking Principle, say the

intellectualists. I myself have contended that they _do not exist_ in

or alongside of the higher mental function when that exists. The things

which arouse them exist; and the higher mental function also knows

these same things. But just as its knowledge of the things supersedes

and displaces their knowledge, so it supersedes and displaces them,

when it comes, being as much as they are a direct resultant of whatever

momentary brain-conditions may obtain. The psychological theory of

contrast, on the other hand, holds the sensations still to exist in

themselves unchanged before the mind, whilst the 'relating activity' of

the latter deals with them freely and settles to its own satisfaction

what each shall be, in view of what the others also are. Wundt says

expressly that the Law of Relativity is "not a law of sensation but

a law of Apperception;" and the word Apperception connotes with him

a higher intellectual spontaneity.[32] This way of taking things

belongs with the philosophy that looks at the _data_ of sense as

something earth-born and servile, and the 'relating of them together'

as something spiritual and free. Lo! the spirit can even change the

intrinsic quality of the sensible facts themselves if by so doing it

can relate them better to each other! But (apart from the difficulty of

seeing how changing the sensations should relate them better) is it not

manifest that the relations are part of the 'content' of consciousness,

part of the 'object,' just as much as the sensations are? Why ascribe

the former exclusively to the _knower_ and the latter to the _known_?

The _knower_ is in every case a unique pulse of thought corresponding

to a unique reaction of the brain upon its conditions. All that the

facts of contrast show us is that the _same real thing_ may give us

quite different sensations when the conditions alter, and that we

must therefore be careful which one to select as the thing's truest

representative.

       *       *       *       *       *

_There are many other facts beside the phenomena of contrast_ which

prove that _when two objects act together on us the sensation which

either would give alone becomes a different sensation_. A certain

amount of skin dipped in hot water gives the perception of a certain

heat. More skin immersed makes the heat much more intense, although

of course the water's heat is the same. A certain extent as well

as intensity, in the quantity of the stimulus is requisite for any

quality to be felt. Fick and Wunderli could not distinguish heat

from touch when both were applied through a hole in a card, and so

confined to a small part of the skin. Similarly there is a _chromatic

minimum_ of size in objects. The image they cast on the retina must

needs have a certain extent, or it will give no sensation of color

at all. Inversely, more intensity in the outward impression may make

the subjective object more extensive. This happens, as will be shown

in Chapter XIX, when the illumination is increased: The whole room

expands and dwindles according as we raise or lower the gas-jet. It is

not easy to explain any of these results as illusions of judgment due

to the inference of a wrong objective cause for the sensation which we

get. No more is this easy in the case of Weber's observation that a

thaler laid on the skin of the forehead feels heavier when cold than

when warm; or of Szabadföldi's observation that small wooden disks

when heated to 122° Fahrenheit often feel heavier than those which are

larger but not thus warmed;[33] or of Hall's observation that a heavy

point moving over the skin seems to go faster than a lighter one moving

at the same rate of speed.[34]

Bleuler and Lehmann some years ago called attention to a strange

idiosyncrasy found in some persons, and consisting in the fact that

impressions on the eye, skin, etc., were accompanied by distinct

sensations of _sound_.[35] _Colored hearing_ is the name sometimes

given to the phenomenon, which has now been repeatedly described. Quite

lately the Viennese aurist Urbantschitsch has proved that these cases

are only extreme examples of a very general law, and that all our

sense-organs influence each other's sensations.[36] The hue of patches

of color so distant as not to be recognized was immediately, in U.'s

patients, perceived when a tuning-fork was sounded close to the ear.

Sometimes, on the contrary, the field was darkened by the sound. The

acuity of vision was increased, so that letters too far off to be read

could be read when the tuning-fork was heard. Urbantschitsch, varying

his experiments, found that their results were mutual, and that sounds

which were on the limits of audibility became audible when lights of

various colors were exhibited to the eye. Smell, taste, touch, sense

of temperature, etc., were all found to fluctuate when lights were

seen and sounds were heard. Individuals varied much in the degree and

kind of effect produced, but almost every one experimented on seems to

have been in some way affected. The phenomena remind one somewhat of

the 'dynamogenic' effects of sensations upon the strength of muscular

contraction observed by M. Féré, and later to be described. The most

familiar examples of them seem to be the increase of _pain_ by noise

or light, and the increase of _nausea_ by all concomitant sensations.

Persons suffering in any way instinctively seek stillness and darkness.

       *       *       *       *       *

Probably every one will agree that the best way of formulating all such

facts is physiological: it must be that the cerebral process of the

first sensation is reinforced or otherwise altered by the other current

which comes in. No one, surely, will prefer a psychological explanation

_here_. Well, it seems to me that _all_ cases of mental reaction

to a plurality of stimuli must be like these cases, and that the

physiological formulation is everywhere the simplest and the best. When

simultaneous red and green light make us see yellow, when three notes

of the scale make us hear a chord, it is not because the sensations of

red and of green and of each of the three notes enter the mind as such,

and there 'combine' or 'are combined by its relating activity' into

the yellow and the chord, it is because the larger sum of light-waves

and of air-waves arouses new cortical processes, to which the yellow

and the chord directly correspond. Even when the sensible qualities of

things enter into the objects of our highest thinking, it is surely

the same. Their several _sensations_ do not continue to exist there

tucked away. They are _replaced_ by the higher thought which, although

a different psychic unit from them, knows the same sensible qualities

which they know.

The principles laid down in Chapter VI seem then to be corroborated in

this new connection. _You cannot build up one thought or one sensation

out of many; and only direct experiment can inform us of what we shall

perceive when we get many stimuli at once._

THE 'ECCENTRIC PROJECTION' OF SENSATIONS.

We often hear the opinion expressed that all our sensations at first

appear to us as subjective or internal, and are afterwards and by a

special act on our part 'extradited' or 'projected' so as to appear

located in an outer world. Thus we read in Professor Ladd's valuable

work that

 "Sensations... are psychical states _whose place_--so far as they

 can be said to have one--_is the mind_. The transference of these

 sensations from mere mental states to physical processes located

 in the periphery of the body, or to qualities of things projected

 in space external to the body, is a mental act. It may rather be

 said to be a mental _achievement_ [cf. Cudworth, footnote 10,

 as to knowledge being _conquering_], for it is an act which in

 its perfection results from a long and intricate process of

 development.... Two noteworthy stages, or 'epoch-making' achievements

 in the process of elaborating the presentations of sense, require a

 special consideration. These are '_localization_,' or the transference

 of the composite sensations from mere states of the mind to processes

 or conditions recognized as taking place at more or less definitely

 fixed points or areas of the body; and '_eccentric projection_'

 (sometimes called 'eccentric perception') or the giving to these

 sensations an objective existence (in the fullest sense of the word

 'objective') as qualities of objects situated within a field of space

 and in contact with, or more or less remotely distant from, the

 body."[37]

It seems to me that there is not a vestige of evidence for this view.

It hangs together with the opinion that our sensations are originally