“
As
this paper contains nothing which deserves the name either of
experiment or discovery, and as it is, in fact, destitute of every
species of merit, we should have allowed it to pass among the
multitude of those articles which must always find their way into
the
collections of a society which is pledged to publish two or three
volumes every year. . . . We wish to raise our feeble voice
against innovations, that can have no other effect than to check
the
progress of science, and renew all those wild phantoms of the
imagination which Bacon and Newton put to flight from her
temple.”
—Opening
Paragraph of a Review of Dr. Young’s Bakerian Lecture.
Edinburgh Review,
January 1803, p.
450.
“
Young’s
work was laid before the Royal society, and was made the 1801
Bakerian Lecture. But he was before his time. The second
number of the
Edinburgh Review
contained an article levelled against him by Henry (afterwards
Lord)
Brougham, and this was so severe an attack that Young’s ideas were
absolutely quenched for fifteen years. Brougham was then only
twenty-four years of age. Young’s theory was reproduced in
France by Fresnel. In our days it is the accepted theory, and
is found to explain all the phenomena of light.”
—Times
Report of a Lecture by Professor Tyndall on Light,
April 27, 1880.
Introduction
By Marcus Hartog
In reviewing Samuel Butler’s
works, “Unconscious Memory” gives us an invaluable lead; for it
tells us (Chaps. II, III) how the author came to write the Book of
the Machines in “Erewhon” (1872), with its foreshadowing of the
later theory, “Life and Habit,” (1878), “Evolution, Old and New”
(1879), as well as “Unconscious Memory” (1880) itself. His fourth
book on biological theory was “Luck? or Cunning?” (1887).[0a]Besides these books, his contributions to biology comprise
several essays: “Remarks on Romanes’Mental Evolution
in Animals, contained in “Selections from Previous
Works” (1884) incorporated into “Luck? or Cunning,” “The Deadlock
in Darwinism” (Universal Review,
April-June, 1890), republished in the posthumous volume of “Essays
on Life, Art, and Science” (1904), and, finally, some of the
“Extracts from the Notebooks of the late Samuel Butler,” edited by
Mr. H. Festing Jones, now in course of publication in theNew Quarterly Review.Of all these, “LIFE AND HABIT” (1878) is the most important,
the main building to which the other writings are buttresses or, at
most, annexes. Its teaching has been summarised in “Unconscious
Memory” in four main principles: “(1) the oneness of personality
between parent and offspring; (2) memory on the part of the
offspring of certain actions which it did when in the persons of
its forefathers; (3) the latency of that memory until it is
rekindled by a recurrence of the associated ideas; (4) the
unconsciousness with which habitual actions come to be performed.”
To these we must add a fifth: the purposiveness of the actions of
living beings, as of the machines which they make or
select.Butler tells (“Life and Habit,” p. 33) that he sometimes
hoped “that this book would be regarded as a valuable adjunct to
Darwinism.” He was bitterly disappointed in the event, for the
book, as a whole, was received by professional biologists as a
gigantic joke—a joke, moreover, not in the best possible taste.
True, its central ideas, largely those of Lamarck, had been
presented by Hering in 1870 (as Butler found shortly after his
publication); they had been favourably received, developed by
Haeckel, expounded and praised by Ray Lankester. Coming from
Butler, they met with contumely, even from such men as Romanes,
who, as Butler had no difficulty in proving, were unconsciously
inspired by the same ideas—“Nur mit ein bischen
ander’n Wörter.”It is easy, looking back, to see why “Life and Habit” so
missed its mark. Charles Darwin’s presentation of the evolution
theory had, for the first time, rendered it possible for a “sound
naturalist” to accept the doctrine of common descent with
divergence; and so given a real meaning to the term “natural
relationship,” which had forced itself upon the older naturalists,
despite their belief in special and independent creations. The
immediate aim of the naturalists of the day was now to fill up the
gaps in their knowledge, so as to strengthen the fabric of a
unified biology. For this purpose they found their actual
scientific equipment so inadequate that they were fully occupied in
inventing fresh technique, and working therewith at facts—save a
few critics, such as St. George Mivart, who was regarded as
negligible, since he evidently held a brief for a party standing
outside the scientific world.Butler introduced himself as what we now call “The Man in the
Street,” far too bare of scientific clothing to satisfy the Mrs.
Grundy of the domain: lacking all recognised tools of science and
all sense of the difficulties in his way, he proceeded to tackle
the problems of science with little save the deft pen of the
literary expert in his hand. His very failure to appreciate the
difficulties gave greater power to his work—much as Tartarin of
Tarascon ascended the Jungfrau and faced successfully all dangers
of Alpine travel, so long as he believed them to be the mere
“blagues de réclame” of the wily Swiss host. His brilliant
qualities of style and irony themselves told heavily against him.
Was he not already known for having written the most trenchant
satire that had appeared since “Gulliver’s Travels”? Had he not
sneered therein at the very foundations of society, and followed up
its success by a pseudo-biography that had taken in the “Record”
and the “Rock”? In “Life and Habit,” at the very start, he goes out
of his way to heap scorn at the respected names of Marcus Aurelius,
Lord Bacon, Goethe, Arnold of Rugby, and Dr. W. B. Carpenter. He
expressed the lowest opinion of the Fellows of the Royal Society.
To him the professional man of science, with self-conscious
knowledge for his ideal and aim, was a medicine-man, priest,
augur—useful, perhaps, in his way, but to be carefully watched by
all who value freedom of thought and person, lest with opportunity
he develop into a persecutor of the worst type. Not content with
blackguarding the audience to whom his work should most appeal, he
went on to depreciate that work itself and its author in his finest
vein of irony. Having argued that our best and highest knowledge is
that of whose possession we are most ignorant, he proceeds: “Above
all, let no unwary reader do me the injustice of believing in me.
In that I write at all I am among the damned.”His writing of “EVOLUTION, OLD AND NEW” (1879) was due to his
conviction that scant justice had been done by Charles Darwin and
Alfred Wallace and their admirers to the pioneering work of Buffon,
Erasmus Darwin, and Lamarck. To repair this he gives a brilliant
exposition of what seemed to him the most valuable portion of their
teachings on evolution. His analysis of Buffon’s true meaning,
veiled by the reticences due to the conditions under which he
wrote, is as masterly as the English in which he develops it. His
sense of wounded justice explains the vigorous polemic which here,
as in all his later writings, he carries to the extreme.As a matter of fact, he never realised Charles Darwin’s utter
lack of sympathetic understanding of the work of his French
precursors, let alone his own grandfather, Erasmus. Yet this
practical ignorance, which to Butler was so strange as to transcend
belief, was altogether genuine, and easy to realise when we recall
the position of Natural Science in the early thirties in Darwin’s
student days at Cambridge, and for a decade or two later.
Catastropharianism was the tenet of the day: to the last it
commended itself to his Professors of Botany and Geology,—for whom
Darwin held the fervent allegiance of the Indian scholar, orchela, to hisguru.
As Geikie has recently pointed out, it was only later, when Lyell
had shown that the breaks in the succession of the rocks were only
partial and local, without involving the universal catastrophes
that destroyed all life and rendered fresh creations thereof
necessary, that any general acceptance of a descent theory could be
expected. We may be very sure that Darwin must have received many
solemn warnings against the dangerous speculations of the “French
Revolutionary School.” He himself was far too busy at the time with
the reception and assimilation of new facts to be awake to the
deeper interest of far-reaching theories.It is the more unfortunate that Butler’s lack of appreciation
on these points should have led to the enormous proportion of
bitter personal controversy that we find in the remainder of his
biological writings. Possibly, as suggested by George Bernard Shaw,
his acquaintance and admirer, he was also swayed by philosophical
resentment at that banishment of mind from the organic universe,
which was generally thought to have been achieved by Charles
Darwin’s theory. Still, we must remember that this mindless view is
not implicit in Charles Darwin’s presentment of his own theory, nor
was it accepted by him as it has been by so many of his professed
disciples.
“ UNCONSCIOUS MEMORY” (1880).—We have already alluded to an
anticipation of Butler’s main theses. In 1870 Dr. Ewald Hering, one
of the most eminent physiologists of the day, Professor at Vienna,
gave an Inaugural Address to the Imperial Royal Academy of
Sciences: “Das Gedächtniss als allgemeine Funktion der organisirter
Substanz” (“Memory as a Universal Function of Organised Matter”).
When “Life and Habit” was well advanced, Francis Darwin, at the
time a frequent visitor, called Butler’s attention to this essay,
which he himself only knew from an article in “Nature.” Herein
Professor E. Ray Lankester had referred to it with admiring
sympathy in connection with its further development by Haeckel in a
pamphlet entitled “Die Perigenese der Plastidule.” We may note,
however, that in his collected Essays, “The Advancement of Science”
(1890), Sir Ray Lankester, while including this Essay, inserts on
the blank page[0b]—we had almost written “the white sheet”—at the back of it an
apology for having ever advocated the possibility of the
transmission of acquired characters.
“ Unconscious Memory” was largely written to show the
relation of Butler’s views to Hering’s, and contains an exquisitely
written translation of the Address. Hering does, indeed, anticipate
Butler, and that in language far more suitable to the persuasion of
the scientific public. It contains a subsidiary hypothesis that
memory has for its mechanism special vibrations of the protoplasm,
and the acquired capacity to respond to such vibrations once felt
upon their repetition. I do not think that the theory gains
anything by the introduction of this even as a mere formal
hypothesis; and there is no evidence for its being anything more.
Butler, however, gives it a warm, nay, enthusiastic, reception in
Chapter V (Introduction to Professor Hering’s lecture), and in his
notes to the translation of the Address, which bulks so large in
this book, but points out that he was “not committed to this
hypothesis, though inclined to accept it on aprima
facieview.” Later on, as we shall see, he attached
more importance to it.The Hering Address is followed in “Unconscious Memory” by
translations of selected passages from Von Hartmann’s “Philosophy
of the Unconscious,” and annotations to explain the difference from
this personification of “The Unconscious” as a mighty all-ruling, all-creating personality, and his
own scientific recognition of the great part played byunconscious processesin the region of mind and
memory.These are the essentials of the book as a contribution to
biological philosophy. The closing chapters contain a lucid
statement of objections to his theory as they might be put by a
rigid necessitarian, and a refutation of that interpretation as
applied to human action.But in the second chapter Butler states his recession from
the strong logical position he had hitherto developed in his
writings from “Erewhon” onwards; so far he had not only
distinguished the living from the non-living, but distinguished
among the lattermachinesortoolsfromthings at large.[0c]Machines or tools are the external organs of living beings,
as organs are their internal machines: they are fashioned,
assembled, or selected by the beings for a purposes so they have
afuture purpose, as well as apast history. “Things at large” have a past
history, but no purpose (so long as some being does not convert
them into tools and give them a purpose): Machines have a Why? as
well as a How?: “things at large” have a How? only.In “Unconscious Memory” the allurements of unitary or
monistic views have gained the upper hand, and Butler writes (p.
23):—
“ The only thing of which I am sure is, that the distinction
between the organic and inorganic is arbitrary; that it is more
coherent with our other ideas, and therefore more acceptable, to
start with every molecule as a living thing, and then deduce death
as the breaking up of an association or corporation, than to start
with inanimate molecules and smuggle life into them; and that,
therefore, what we call the inorganic world must be regarded as up
to a certain point living, and instinct, within certain limits,
with consciousness, volition, and power of concerted action.It is only of late,however,that I have come to this opinion.”I have italicised the last sentence, to show that Butler was
more or less conscious of its irreconcilability with much of his
most characteristic doctrine. Again, in the closing chapter, Butler
writes (p. 275):—
“ We should endeavour to see the so-called inorganic as
living in respect of the qualities it has in common with the
organic, rather than the organic as non-living in respect of the
qualities it has in common with the inorganic.”We conclude our survey of this book by mentioning the
literary controversial part chiefly to be found in Chapter IV, but
cropping up elsewhere. It refers to interpolations made in the
authorised translation of Krause’s “Life of Erasmus Darwin.” Only
one side is presented; and we are not called upon, here or
elsewhere, to discuss the merits of the question.
“ LUCK, OR CUNNING, as the Main Means of Organic
Modification? an Attempt to throw Additional Light upon the late
Mr. Charles Darwin’s Theory of Natural Selection” (1887), completes
the series of biological books. This is mainly a book of strenuous
polemic. It brings out still more forcibly the Hering-Butler
doctrine of continued personality from generation to generation,
and of the working of unconscious memory throughout; and points out
that, while this is implicit in much of the teaching of Herbert
Spencer, Romanes, and others, it was nowhere—even after the
appearance of “Life and Habit”—explicitly recognised by them, but,
on the contrary, masked by inconsistent statements and teaching.
Not Luck but Cunning, not the uninspired weeding out by Natural
Selection but the intelligent striving of the organism, is at the
bottom of the useful variety of organic life. And the parallel is
drawn that not the happy accident of time and place, but the
Machiavellian cunning of Charles Darwin, succeeded in imposing, as
entirely his own, on the civilised world an uninspired and
inadequate theory of evolution wherein luck played the leading
part; while the more inspired and inspiring views of the older
evolutionists had failed by the inferiority of their luck. On this
controversy I am bound to say that I do not in the very least share
Butler’s opinions; and I must ascribe them to his lack of personal
familiarity with the biologists of the day and their modes of
thought and of work. Butler everywhere undervalues the important
work of elimination played by Natural Selection in its widest
sense.The “Conclusion” of “Luck, or Cunning?” shows a strong
advance in monistic views, and a yet more marked development in the
vibration hypothesis of memory given by Hering and only adopted
with the greatest reserve in “Unconscious Memory.”
“ Our conception, then, concerning the nature of any matter
depends solely upon its kind and degree of unrest, that is to say,
on the characteristics of the vibrations that are going on within
it. The exterior object vibrating in a certain way imparts some of
its vibrations to our brain; but if the state of the thing itself
depends upon its vibrations, it [the thing] must be considered as
to all intents and purposes the vibrations themselves—plus, of
course, the underlying substance that is vibrating. . . . The same
vibrations, therefore, form the substance remembered, introduce an
infinitesimal dose of it within the brain, modify the substance
remembering, and, in the course of time, create and further modify
the mechanism of both the sensory and the motor nerves. Thought and
thing are one.
“ I commend these two last speculations to the reader’s
charitable consideration, as feeling that I am here travelling
beyond the ground on which I can safely venture. . . . I believe
they are both substantially true.”In 1885 he had written an abstract of these ideas in his
notebooks (seeNew Quarterly Review,
1910, p. 116), and as in “Luck, or Cunning?” associated them
vaguely with the unitary conceptions introduced into chemistry by
Newlands and Mendelejeff. Judging himself as an outsider, the
author of “Life and Habit” would certainly have considered the mild
expression of faith, “I believe they are both substantially true,”
equivalent to one of extreme doubt. Thus “the fact of the
Archbishop’s recognising this as among the number of his beliefs is
conclusive evidence, with those who have devoted attention to the
laws of thought, that his mind is not yet clear” on the matter of
the belief avowed (see “Life and Habit,” pp. 24, 25).To sum up: Butler’s fundamental attitude to the vibration
hypothesis was all through that taken in “Unconscious Memory”; he
played with it as a pretty pet, and fancied it more and more as
time went on; but instead of backing it for all he was worth, like
the main theses of “Life and Habit,” he put a big stake on it—and
then hedged.The last of Butler’s biological writings is the Essay, “THE
DEADLOCK IN DARWINISM,” containing much valuable criticism on
Wallace and Weismann. It is in allusion to the misnomer of
Wallace’s book, “Darwinism,” that he introduces the term
“Wallaceism”[0d]for a theory of descent that excludes the transmission of
acquired characters. This was, indeed, the chief factor that led
Charles Darwin to invent his hypothesis of pangenesis, which,
unacceptable as it has proved, had far more to recommend it as a
formal hypothesis than the equally formal germ-plasm hypothesis of
Weismann.The chief difficulty in accepting the main theses of Butler
and Hering is one familiar to every biologist, and not at all
difficult to understand by the layman. Everyone knows that the
complicated beings that we term “Animals” and “Plants,” consist of
a number of more or less individualised units, the cells, each
analogous to a simpler being, a Protist—save in so far as the
character of the cell unit of the Higher being is modified in
accordance with the part it plays in that complex being as a whole.
Most people, too, are familiar with the fact that the complex being
starts as a single cell, separated from its parent; or, where
bisexual reproduction occurs, from a cell due to the fusion of two
cells, each detached from its parent. Such cells are called
“Germ-cells.” The germ-cell, whether of single or of dual origin,
starts by dividing repeatedly, so as to form theprimary embryonic cells, a complex mass of
cells, at first essentially similar, which, however, as they go on
multiplying, undergo differentiations and migrations, losing their
simplicity as they do so. Those cells that are modified to take
part in the proper work of the whole are called tissue-cells. In
virtue of their activities, their growth and reproductive power are
limited—much more in Animals than in Plants, in Higher than in
Lower beings. It is these tissues, or some of them, that receive
the impressions from the outside which leave the imprint of memory.
Other cells, which may be closely associated into a continuous
organ, or more or less surrounded by tissue-cells, whose part it is
to nourish them, are called “secondary embryonic cells,” or
“germ-cells.” The germ-cells may be differentiated in the young
organism at a very early stage, but in Plants they are separated at
a much later date from the less isolated embryonic regions that
provide for the Plant’s branching; in all cases we find embryonic
and germ-cells screened from the life processes of the complex
organism, or taking no very obvious part in it, save to form new
tissues or new organs, notably in Plants.Again, in ourselves, and to a greater or less extent in all
Animals, we find a system of special tissues set apart for the
reception and storage of impressions from the outer world, and for
guiding the other organs in their appropriate responses—the
“Nervous System”; and when this system is ill-developed or out of
gear the remaining organs work badly from lack of proper skilled
guidance and co-ordination. How can we, then, speak of “memory” in
a germ-cell which has been screened from the experiences of the
organism, which is too simple in structure to realise them if it
were exposed to them? My own answer is that we cannot form any
theory on the subject, the only question is whether we have any
right toinferthis “memory” from
thebehaviourof living beings; and
Butler, like Hering, Haeckel, and some more modern authors, has
shown that the inference is a very strong presumption. Again, it is
easy to over-value such complex instruments as we possess. The
possessor of an up-to-date camera, well instructed in the function
and manipulation of every part, but ignorant of all optics save a
hand-to-mouth knowledge of the properties of his own lens, might
say thata priorino picture could be
taken with a cigar-box perforated by a pin-hole; and our ignorance
of the mechanism of the Psychology of any organism is greater by
many times than that of my supposed photographer. We know that
Plants are able to do many things that can only be accounted for by
ascribing to them a “psyche,” and these co-ordinated enough to
satisfy their needs; and yet they possess no central organ
comparable to the brain, no highly specialised system for
intercommunication like our nerve trunks and fibres. As Oscar
Hertwig says, we are as ignorant of the mechanism of the
development of the individual as we are of that of hereditary
transmission of acquired characters, and the absence of such
mechanism in either case is no reason for rejecting the proven
fact.However, the relations of germ and body just described led
Jäger, Nussbaum, Galton, Lankester, and, above all, Weismann, to
the view that the germ-cells or “stirp” (Galton) wereinthe body, but notofit. Indeed, in the body and out of it, whether as
reproductive cells set free, or in the developing embryo, they are
regarded as forming one continuous homogeneity, in contrast to the
differentiation of the body; and it is to these cells, regarded as
a continuum, that the terms stirp, germ-plasm, are especially
applied. Yet on this view, so eagerly advocated by its supporters,
we have to substitute for the hypothesis of memory, which they
declare to have no real meaning here, the far more fantastic
hypotheses of Weismann: by these they explain the process of
differentiation in the young embryo into new germ and body; and in
the young body the differentiation of its cells, each in due time
and place, into the varied tissue cells and organs. Such views
might perhaps be acceptable if it could be shown that over each
cell-division there presided a wise all-guiding genie of
transcending intellect, to which Clerk-Maxwell’s sorting demons
were mere infants. Yet these views have so enchanted many
distinguished biologists, that in dealing with the subject they
have actually ignored the existence of equally able workers who
hesitate to share the extremest of their views. The phenomenon is
one well known in hypnotic practice. So long as the
non-Weismannians deal with matters outside this discussion, their
existence and their work is rated at its just value; but any work
of theirs on this point so affects the orthodox Weismannite
(whether he accept this label or reject it does not matter), that
for the time being their existence and the good work they have done
are alike non-existent.[0e]Butler founded no school, and wished to found none. He
desired that what was true in his work should prevail, and he
looked forward calmly to the time when the recognition of that
truth and of his share in advancing it should give him in the lives
of others that immortality for which alone he craved.Lamarckian views have never lacked defenders here and in
America. Of the English, Herbert Spencer, who however, was averse
to the vitalistic attitude, Vines and Henslow among botanists,
Cunningham among zoologists, have always resisted Weismannism; but,
I think, none of these was distinctly influenced by Hering and
Butler. In America the majority of the great school of
palæontologists have been strong Lamarckians, notably Cope, who has
pointed out, moreover, that the transformations of energy in living
beings are peculiar to them.We have already adverted to Haeckel’s acceptance and
development of Hering’s ideas in his “Perigenese der Plastidule.”
Oscar Hertwig has been a consistent Lamarckian, like Yves Delage of
the Sorbonne, and these occupy pre-eminent positions not only as
observers, but as discriminating theorists and historians of the
recent progress of biology. We may also cite as a Lamarckian—of a
sort—Felix Le Dantec, the leader of the chemico-physical school of
the present day.But we must seek elsewhere for special attention to the
points which Butler regarded as the essentials of “Life and Habit.”
In 1893 Henry P. Orr, Professor of Biology in the University of
Louisiana, published a little book entitled “A Theory of Heredity.”
Herein he insists on the nervous control of the whole body, and on
the transmission to the reproductive cells of such stimuli,
received by the body, as will guide them on their path until they
shall have acquired adequate experience of their own in the new
body they have formed. I have found the name of neither Butler nor
Hering, but the treatment is essentially on their lines, and is
both clear and interesting.In 1896 I wrote an essay on “The Fundamental Principles of
Heredity,” primarily directed to the man in the street. This, after
being held over for more than a year by one leading review, was
“declined with regret,” and again after some weeks met the same
fate from another editor. It appeared in the pages of “Natural
Science” for October, 1897, and in the “Biologisches Centralblatt”
for the same year. I reproduce its closing paragraph:—
“ This theory [Hering-Butler’s] has, indeed, a tentative
character, and lacks symmetrical completeness, but is the more
welcome as not aiming at the impossible. A whole series of
phenomena in organic beings are correlated under the term ofmemory,conscious and
unconscious,patent and latent. . . . Of the order of unconscious memory, latent till the
arrival of the appropriate stimulus, is all the co-operative growth
and work of the organism, including its development from the
reproductive cells. Concerning themodus
operandiwe know nothing: the phenomena may be due, as
Hering suggests, to molecular vibrations, which must be at least as
distinct from ordinary physical disturbances as Röntgen’s rays are
from ordinary light; or it may be correlated, as we ourselves are
inclined to think, with complex chemical changes in an intricate
but orderly succession. For the present, at least, the problem of
heredity can only be elucidated by the light of mental, and not
material processes.”It will be seen that I express doubts as to the validity of
Hering’s invocation of molecular vibrations as the mechanism of
memory, and suggest as an alternative rhythmic chemical changes.
This view has recently been put forth in detail by J. J. Cunningham
in his essay on the “Hormone[0f]Theory of Heredity,” in theArchiv für
Entwicklungsmechanik(1909), but I have failed to note
any direct effect of my essay on the trend of biological
thought.Among post-Darwinian controversies the one that has latterly
assumed the greatest prominence is that of the relative importance
of small variations in the way of more or less “fluctuations,” and
of “discontinuous variations,” or “mutations,” as De Vries has
called them. Darwin, in the first four editions of the “Origin of
Species,” attached more importance to the latter than in subsequent
editions; he was swayed in his attitude, as is well known, by an
article of the physicist, Fleeming Jenkin, which appeared in
theNorth British Review. The
mathematics of this article were unimpeachable, but they were
founded on the assumption that exceptional variations would only
occur in single individuals, which is, indeed, often the case among
those domesticated races on which Darwin especially studied the
phenomena of variation. Darwin was no mathematician or physicist,
and we are told in his biography that he regarded every tool-shop
rule or optician’s thermometer as an instrument of precision: so he
appears to have regarded Fleeming Jenkin’s demonstration as a
mathematical deduction which he was bound to accept without
criticism.Mr. William Bateson, late Professor of Biology in the
University of Cambridge, as early as 1894 laid great stress on the
importance of discontinuous variations, collecting and collating
the known facts in his “Materials for the Study of Variations”; but
this important work, now become rare and valuable, at the time
excited so little interest as to be ‘remaindered’ within a very few
years after publication.In 1901 Hugo De Vries, Professor of Botany in the University
of Amsterdam, published “Die Mutationstheorie,” wherein he showed
that mutations or discontinuous variations in various directions
may appear simultaneously in many individuals, and in various
directions. In the gardener’s phrase, the species may take to
sporting in various directions at the same time, and each sport may
be represented by numerous specimens.De Vries shows the probability that species go on for long
periods showing only fluctuations, and then suddenly take to
sporting in the way described, short periods of mutation
alternating with long intervals of relative constancy. It is to
mutations that De Vries and his school, as well as Luther Burbank,
the great former of new fruit- and flower-plants, look for those
variations which form the material of Natural Selection. In “God
the Known and God the Unknown,” which appeared in theExaminer(May, June, and July), 1879, but though
then revised was only published posthumously in 1909, Butler
anticipates this distinction:—
“ Under these circumstances organism must act in one or other
of these two ways: it must either change slowly and continuously
with the surroundings, paying cash for everything, meeting the
smallest change with a corresponding modification, so far as is
found convenient, or it must put off change as long as possible,
and then make larger and more sweeping changes.
“ Both these courses are the same in principle, the
difference being one of scale, and the one being a miniature of the
other, as a ripple is an Atlantic wave in little; both have their
advantages and disadvantages, so that most organisms will take the
one course for one set of things and the other for another. They
will deal promptly with things which they can get at easily, and
which lie more upon the surface;those,however,which are
more troublesome to reach,and lie
deeper,will be handled upon more
cataclysmic principles,being allowed
longer periods of repose followed by short periods of greater
activity. . . it may be questioned whether what is
called a sport is not the organic expression of discontent which
has been long felt, but which has not been attended to, nor been
met step by step by as much small remedial modification as was
found practicable: so that when a change does come it comes by way
of revolution. Or, again (only that it comes to much the same
thing), it may be compared to one of those happy thoughts which
sometimes come to us unbidden after we have been thinking for a
long time what to do, or how to arrange our ideas, and have yet
been unable to come to any conclusion” (pp. 14, 15).[0g]We come to another order of mind in Hans Driesch. At the time
he began his work biologists were largely busy in a region
indicated by Darwin, and roughly mapped out by Haeckel—that of
phylogeny. From the facts of development of the individual, from
the comparison of fossils in successive strata, they set to work at
the construction of pedigrees, and strove to bring into line the
principles of classification with the more or less hypothetical
“stemtrees.” Driesch considered this futile, since we never could
reconstruct from such evidence anything certain in the history of
the past. He therefore asserted that a more complete knowledge of
the physics and chemistry of the organic world might give a
scientific explanation of the phenomena, and maintained that the
proper work of the biologist was to deepen our knowledge in these
respects. He embodied his views, seeking the explanation on this
track, filling up gaps and tracing projected roads along lines of
probable truth in his “Analytische Theorie der organische
Entwicklung.” But his own work convinced him of the hopelessness of
the task he had undertaken, and he has become as strenuous a
vitalist as Butler. The most complete statement of his present
views is to be found in “The Philosophy of Life” (1908–9), being
the Giffold Lectures for 1907–8. Herein he postulates a quality
(“psychoid”) in all living beings, directing energy and matter for
the purpose of the organism, and to this he applies the
Aristotelian designation “Entelechy.” The question of the
transmission of acquired characters is regarded as doubtful, and he
does not emphasise—if he accepts—the doctrine of continuous
personality. His early youthful impatience with descent theories
and hypotheses has, however, disappeared.In the next work the influence of Hering and Butler is
definitely present and recognised. In 1906 Signor Eugenio Rignano,
an engineer keenly interested in all branches of science, and a
little later the founder of the international review,Rivistà di Scienza(now simply calledScientia), published in French a volume
entitled “Sur la transmissibilité des Caractères acquis—Hypothèse
d’un Centro-épigenèse.” Into the details of the author’s work we
will not enter fully. Suffice it to know that he accepts the
Hering-Butler theory, and makes a distinct advance on Hering’s
rather crude hypothesis of persistent vibrations by suggesting that
the remembering centres store slightly different forms of energy,
to give out energy of the same kind as they have received, like
electrical accumulators. The last chapter, “Le Phénomène mnémonique
et le Phénomène vital,” is frankly based on Hering.In “The Lesson of Evolution” (1907, posthumous, and only
published for private circulation) Frederick Wollaston Hutton,
F.R.S., late Professor of Biology and Geology, first at Dunedin and
after at Christchurch, New Zealand, puts forward a strongly
vitalistic view, and adopts Hering’s teaching. After stating this
he adds, “The same idea of heredity being due to unconscious memory
was advocated by Mr. Samuel Butler in his “Life and
Habit.”Dr. James Mark Baldwin, Stuart Professor of Psychology in
Princeton University, U.S.A., called attention early in the 90’s to
a reaction characteristic of all living beings, which he terms the
“Circular Reaction.” We take his most recent account of this from
his “Development and Evolution” (1902):—[0h]
“ The general fact is that the organism reacts by
concentration upon the locality stimulated for thecontinuanceof the conditions, movements,
stimulations,which are vitally beneficial, and for the cessation of the conditions, movements,
stimulationswhich are vitally depressing.”This amounts to saying in the terminology of Jenning (see
below) that the living organism alters its “physiological states”
either for its direct benefit, or for its indirect benefit in the
reduction of harmful conditions.Again:—
“ This form of concentration of energy on stimulated
localities, with the resulting renewal through movement of
conditions that are pleasure-giving and beneficial, and the
consequent repetition of the movements is called ‘circular
reaction.’”Of course, the inhibition of such movements as would be
painful on repetition is merely the negative case of the circular
reaction. We must not put too much of our own ideas into the
author’s mind; he nowhere says explicitly that the animal or plant
shows its sense and does this because it likes the one thing and
wants it repeated, or dislikes the other and stops its repetition,
as Butler would have said. Baldwin is very strong in insisting that
no full explanation can be given of living processes, any more than
of history, on purely chemico-physical grounds.The same view is put differently and independently by H. S.
Jennings,[0i]who started his investigations of living Protista, the
simplest of living beings, with the idea that only accurate and
ample observation was needed to enable us to explain all their
activities on a mechanical basis, and devised ingenious models of
protoplastic movements. He was led, like Driesch, to renounce such
efforts as illusory, and has come to the conviction that in the
behaviour of these lowly beings there is a purposive and a
tentative character—a method of “trial and error”—that can only be
interpreted by the invocation of psychology. He points out that
after stimulation the “state” of the organism may be altered, so
that the response to the same stimulus on repetition is other. Or,
as he puts it, the first stimulus has caused the organism to pass
into a new “physiological state.” As the change of state from what
we may call the “primary indifferent state” is advantageous to the
organism, we may regard this as equivalent to the doctrine of the
“circular reaction,” and also as containing the essence of Semon’s
doctrine of “engrams” or imprints which we are about to consider.
We cite one passage which for audacity of thought (underlying, it
is true, most guarded expression) may well compare with many of the
boldest flights in “Life and Habit”:—
“ It may be noted that regulation in the manner we have set
forth is what, in the behaviour of higher organisms, at least, is
called intelligence [the examples have been taken from Protista,
Corals, and the Lowest Worms]. If the same method of regulation is
found in other fields, there is no reason for refusing to compare
the action to intelligence. Comparison of the regulatory processes
that are shown in internal physiological changes and in
regeneration to intelligence seems to be looked upon sometimes as
heretical and unscientific. Yet intelligence is a name applied to
processes that actually exist in the regulation of movements, and
there is,a priori, no reason why
similar processes should not occur in regulation in other fields.
When we analyse regulation objectively there seems indeed reason to
think that the processes are of the same character in behaviour as
elsewhere. If the term intelligence be reserved for the subjective
accompaniments of such regulation, then of course we have no direct
knowledge of its existence in any of the fields of regulation
outside of the self, and in the self perhaps only in behaviour. But
in a purely objective consideration there seems no reason to
suppose that regulation in behaviour (intelligence) is of a
fundamentally different character from regulation elsewhere.”
(“Method of Regulation,” p. 492.)Jennings makes no mention of questions of the theory of
heredity. He has made some experiments on the transmission of an
acquired character in Protozoa; but it was a mutilation-character,
which is, as has been often shown,[0j]not to the point.One of the most obvious criticisms of Hering’s exposition is
based upon the extended use he makes of the word “Memory”: this he
had foreseen and deprecated.
“ We have a perfect right,” he says, “to extend our
conception of memory so as to make it embrace involuntary [and also
unconscious] reproductions of sensations, ideas, perceptions, and
efforts; but we find, on having done so, that we have so far
enlarged her boundaries that she proves to be an ultimate and
original power, the source and, at the same time, the unifying
bond, of our whole conscious l [...]