Posterior Analytics - Aristotle - E-Book

Posterior Analytics E-Book

Aristotle

0,0
1,99 €

oder
-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

Aristotle's 'Posterior Analytics' is a foundational text in the field of logical theory and epistemology. Written in a concise and systematic style, the book explores the nature of scientific knowledge and the process of acquiring it through demonstration. Aristotle delves into the theory of demonstration, the structure of scientific explanations, and the role of syllogistic reasoning in knowledge acquisition. Drawing on his vast knowledge of natural sciences and metaphysics, Aristotle presents a rigorous and insightful account of the principles of scientific inquiry. His logical analysis of the nature of knowledge continues to be a vital contribution to the history of philosophy. Aristotle, one of the greatest thinkers of ancient Greece, was a student of Plato and a teacher of Alexander the Great. His extensive works encompass philosophy, logic, ethics, politics, metaphysics, and natural sciences. 'Posterior Analytics' is a testament to his profound intellect and enduring influence on Western thought. I highly recommend 'Posterior Analytics' to readers interested in delving into the foundational principles of scientific knowledge and logical reasoning. Aristotle's insightful analysis and systematic approach provide a valuable resource for scholars and students of philosophy and logic.

Das E-Book können Sie in Legimi-Apps oder einer beliebigen App lesen, die das folgende Format unterstützen:

EPUB
Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



Aristotle

Posterior Analytics

 
EAN 8596547158363
DigiCat, 2022 Contact: [email protected]

Table of Contents

Book I.
Book II.
Chapter I: Whether a Demonstrative Science exists
Chapter II: What Knowing is, what Demonstration is, and of what it consists
Chapter III: A refutation of the error into which some have fallen concerning Science and Demonstration
Chapter IV: The meaning of ‘Distributive,’ ‘Essential,’ ‘Universal’
Chapter V: From what causes mistakes arise with regard to the discovery of the Universal. How they may be avoided
Chapter VI: Demonstration is founded on Necessary and Essential Principles
Chapter VII: The Premises and the Conclusion of a Demonstration must belong to the same genus
Chapter VIII: Demonstration is concerned only with what is eternal
Chapter IX: Demonstration is founded not on general, but on special and indemonstrable principles; nor is it easy to know whether one really possesses knowledge drawn from these principles
Chapter X: The Definition and Division of Principles
Chapter XI: On certain Principles which are common to all Sciences
Chapter XII: On Questions, and, in passing, on the way in which Sciences are extended
Chapter XIII: The difference between the Demonstration and Science of a thing’s Nature and those of its Cause
Chapter XIV: The figure proper to Demonstrate Syllogism
Chapter XV: On immediate negative propositions
Chapter XVI: On ignorance resulting from a defective arrangement of terms in mediate propositions
Chapter XVII: On ignorance resulting from a defective arrangement of terms in immediate propositions
Chapter XVIII: On ignorance as resulting from defective sense perception
Chapter XIX: Whether the Principles of Demonstration are finite or infinite
Chapter XX: Middle terms are not infinite
Chapter XXI: In Negations some final and ultimate point is reached where the series must cease
Chapter XXII: In Affirmations some final and ultimate point is reached where the series must cease
Chapter XXIII: Certain Corollaries
Chapter XXIV: Whether Universal or Particular Demonstration is superior
Chapter XXV: That Affirmative is superior to Negative Demonstration
Chapter XXVI: Direct Demonstration is superior to Reduction per impossible
Chapter XXVII: What science is more certain and prior, and what less certain and inferior
Chapter XXVIII: What constitutes one or many Sciences
Chapter XXIX: Concerning many Demonstrations of the same thing
Chapter XXX: On fortuitous occurrences
Chapter XXXI: Sense perception cannot give Demonstrative Science
Chapter XXXII: On the difference of Principles corresponding to the difference of Syllogisms
Chapter XXXIII: The distinction between Science and Opinion
Chapter XXXIV: On Sagacity
Chapter I: On the number and arrangements of Questions
Chapter II: Every question is concerned with the discovery of a Middle Term
Chapter III: The distinction between Definition and Demonstration
Chapter IV: The Essence of a thing cannot be attained by Syllogism
Chapter V: Knowledge of the Essence cannot be attained by Division
Chapter VI: The Essence cannot be proved by the Definition of the thing itself or by that of its opposite
Chapter VII: Whether the Essence can in any way be proved
Chapter VIII: How the Essence can be proved
Chapter IX: What Essences can and what cannot be proved
Chapter X: The nature and forms of Definition
Chapter XI: The kinds of Causes used in Demonstration
Chapter XII: On the Causes of events which exist, are in process, have happened, or will happen
Chapter XIII: On the search for a Definition
Chapter XIV: On the discovery of Questions for Demonstration
Chapter XV: How far the same Middle Term is employed for demonstrating different Questions
Chapter XVI: On inferring the Cause from the Effect
Chapter XVII: Whether there can be several causes of the same thing
Chapter XVIII: Which is the prior cause, that which is nearer the particular, or the more universal?
Chapter XIX: On the attainment of Primary Principles
Appendix

Book I.

Table of Contents

Chap. I.

: Whether a Demonstrative Science exists

Chap. II.

: What Knowing is, what Demonstration is, and of what it consists

Chap. III.

: A refutation of the error into which some have fallen concerning Science and Demonstration

Chap. IV.

: The meaning of ‘Distributive,’ ‘Essential,’ ‘Universal’

Chap. V.

: From what causes mistakes arise with regard to the discovery of the Universal. How they may be avoided

Chap. VI.

: Demonstration is founded on Necessary and Essential Principles

Chap. VII.

: The Premises and the Conclusion of a Demonstration must belong to the same genus

Chap. VIII.

: Demonstration is concerned only with what is eternal

Chap. IX.

: Demonstration is founded not on general, but on special and indemonstrable principles; nor is it easy to know whether one really possesses knowledge drawn from these principles

Chap. X.

: The Definition and Division of Principles

Chap. XI.

: On certain Principles which are common to all Sciences

Chap. XII.

: On Questions, and, in passing, on the way in which Sciences are extended

Chap. XIII.

: The difference between the Demonstration and Science of a thing’s Nature and those of its Cause

Chap. XIV.

: The figure proper to Demonstrate Syllogism

Chap. XV.

: On immediate negative propositions

Chap. XVI.

: On ignorance resulting from a defective arrangement of terms in mediate propositions

Chap. XVII.

: On ignorance resulting from a defective arrangement of terms in immediate propositions

Chap. XVIII.

: On ignorance as resulting from defective sense perception

Chap. XIX.

: Whether the Principles of Demonstration are finite or infinite

Chap. XX.

: Middle terms are not infinite

Chap. XXI.

: In Negations some final and ultimate point is reached where the series must cease

Chap. XXII.

: In Affirmations some final and ultimate point is reached where the series must cease

Chap. XXIII.

: Certain Corollaries

Chap. XXIV.

: Whether Universal or Particular Demonstration is superior

Chap. XXV.

: That Affirmative is superior to Negative Demonstration

Chap. XXVI.

: Direct Demonstration is superior to Reduction per impossible

Chap. XXVII.

: What science is more certain and prior, and what less certain and inferior

Chap. XXVIII.

: What constitutes one or many Sciences

Chap. XXIX.

: Concerning many Demonstrations of the same thing

Chap. XXX.

: On fortuitous occurrences

Chap. XXXI.

: Sense perception cannot give Demonstrative Science

Chap. XXXII.

: On the difference of Principles corresponding to the difference of Syllogisms

Chap. XXXIII.

: The distinction between Science and Opinion

Chap. XXXIV.

: On Sagacity

Book II.

Table of Contents

Chap. I.

: On the number and arrangements of Questions

Chap. II.

: Every question is concerned with the discovery of a Middle Term

Chap. III.

: The distinction between Definition and Demonstration

Chap. IV.

: The Essence of a thing cannot be attained by Syllogism

Chap. V.

: Knowledge of the Essence cannot be attained by Division

Chap. VI.

: The Essence cannot be proved by the Definition of the thing itself or by that of its opposite

Chap. VII.

: Whether the Essence can in any way be proved

Chap. VIII.

: How the Essence can be proved

Chap. IX.

: What Essences can and what cannot be proved

Chap. X.

: The nature and forms of Definition

Chap. XI.

: The kinds of Causes used in Demonstration

Chap. XII.

: On the Causes of events which exist, are in process, have happened, or will happen

Chap. XIII.

: On the search for a Definition

Chap. XIV.

: On the discovery of Questions for Demonstration

Chap. XV.

: How far the same Middle Term is employed for demonstrating different Questions

Chap. XVI.

: On inferring the Cause from the Effect

Chap. XVII.

: Whether there can be several causes of the same thing

Chap. XVIII.

: Which is the prior cause, that which is nearer the particular, or the more universal?

Chap. XIX.

: On the attainment of Primary Principles

Appendix.

Chapter I: Whether a Demonstrative Science exists

Table of Contents

Previous knowledge is required for all scientific studies or methods of instruction. Examples from Mathematics, Dialectic and Rhetoric. Previous knowledge as variously expressed in theses concerning either the existence of a thing or the meaning of the word denoting it. Learning consists in the conversion of universal into particular knowledge.

All communications of knowledge from teacher to pupil by way of reasoning pre-suppose some pre-existing knowledge. The truth of this statement may be seen from a complete enumeration of instances:—it is thus that the mathematical sciences are attained and every art also. The same is the case with dialectical arguments whether proceeding by means of the syllogism or of induction, for the former kind makes such assumptions as people who understand the meaning admit, the latter uses the recognized clearness of the particular as an indication of the universal, so that both convey their information by means of things already known. So too orators produce conviction in a like manner, using either Example, which is equivalent to induction, or Enthymeme, which corresponds to syllogism.

Pre-existing knowledge of two kinds is required: one must either assume beforehand that something exists, or one must understand what the word means, while sometimes both sorts of knowledge are required. As an example of the first case we may take the necessity for previously knowing the proposition ‘everything must be either affirmed or denied.’ Of the second case an instance would be the knowledge of the meaning conveyed by the word ‘triangle’; of the combination of both kinds, the knowledge both of what ‘Unit’ means, and of the fact that ‘Unit’ exists. The distinction is necessary, since the grounds of certainty differ in the two cases.

Some facts become known as a result of previously acquired knowledge, while others are learned at the moment of perceiving the object. This latter happens in the case of all things comprised under a universal, with which one is already acquainted. It is known to the pupil, before perceiving any particular triangle, that the interior angles of every triangle are equal to two right angles; but it is only at the moment of sense-perception that he learns that this figure inscribed in the semi-circle is a triangle.

In some cases knowledge is only acquired in this latter way, and the particular is not learned by means of a middle term: that is to say, in the cases where we touch the concrete particular, that is in the case of things which are not predicable of any subject. We ought to admit that, even before arriving at particulars, and so obtaining a syllogism, we do, from one point of view perhaps, possess knowledge, although from another we do not. For how, it may be asked, when he did not know whether the thing existed at all or not, could he have known absolutely that it contains two right angles? The answer is that he knows it from a particular point of view, in that he knows the universal, but he does not know it absolutely. On any other view we shall have the dilemma of the Meno—a man will either learn nothing at all or only what he knows before. This difficulty must not be solved as some try to do. The question is asked, ‘Do you or do you not know every dyad to be even?’ On receiving an affirmative reply they bring forward some dyad of the existence of which the other was ignorant, and so could not have known it to be even. The solution suggested is to say that one does not know every dyad to be even, but only that which one knows to be a dyad. On the other hand one knows that of which one possesses or has received a demonstration, and no demonstration concerns merely (e.g.) every triangle, or number, one may happen to know, but every possible triangle or number. No demonstrative proposition is taken as referring to ‘any number you may know of,’ or ‘any straight line you may know of,’ but to the entire subject. Nothing, however, I should suppose, precludes our knowing already what we learn from one point of view and not knowing it from another. The absurdity would consist not in having some sort of knowledge of what one learns, but in having knowledge of it in a certain respect—I mean in the very same respect and manner in which one learns it.

Chapter II: What Knowing is, what Demonstration is, and of what it consists

Table of Contents

Scientific knowledge of a thing consists in knowing its cause demonstratively. The principles required for Demonstration. Meaning of ‘Thesis,’ ‘Hypothesis,’ ‘Axiom,’ ‘Definition.’

We suppose ourselves to know anything absolutely and not accidentally after the manner of the sophists, when we consider ourselves to know that the ground from which the thing arises is the ground of it, and that the fact cannot be otherwise. Science must clearly consist in this, for those who suppose themselves to have scientific knowledge of anything without really having it imagine that they are in the position described above, while those who do possess such knowledge are actually in that position in relation to the object.

Hence it follows that everything which admits of absolute knowledge is necessary. We will discuss later the question as to whether there is any other manner of knowing a thing, but at any rate we hold that that ‘knowledge comes through demonstration.’ By ‘demonstration’ I mean a scientific syllogism, and by ‘scientific’ a syllogism the mere possession of which makes us know.

If then the definition of knowledge be such as we have stated, the premises of demonstrative knowledge must needs be true, primary, immediate, better known than, anterior to, and the cause of, the conclusion, for under these conditions the principles will also be appropriate to the conclusion. One may, indeed, have a syllogism without these conditions, but not demonstration, for it will not produce scientific knowledge. The premises must be true, because it is impossible to know that which is not, e.g. that the diagonal of a square is commensurate with the side. The conclusion must proceed from primary premises that are indemonstrable premises, for one cannot know things of which one can give no demonstration, since to know demonstrable things in any real sense is just to have a demonstration of them. The premises must be Causal, Better known and Anterior; Causal, because we only know a thing when we have learned its cause, Anterior because anteriority is implied by causation, previously known not only in our second sense, viz. that their meaning is understood, but that one knows that they exist.

Now the expressions ‘anterior’ and ‘better known’ have each a double meaning; things which are naturally anterior are not the same as things anterior to us, nor yet are things naturally better known better known to us. I mean by things anterior, or better known, ‘to us,’ such as are nearer our sense-perception, while things which are absolutely anterior or better known are such as are more removed from it. Those things are the furthest removed from it which are most Universal, nearest to it stands the Particular, and these two are diametrically opposed.

The phrase ‘the conclusion must result from primary principles’ means that it must come from elements appropriate to itself, (for I attach the same meaning to primary principle [πρτον] and to element [ρχή]). Now the element of demonstration is an immediate proposition; ‘immediate’ meaning a proposition with no other proposition anterior to it. A premise is either of the two parts of a predication, wherein one predicate is asserted of one subject. A dialectical premise is one which offers an alternative between the two parts of the predication, a demonstrative premise is one which lays down definitely that one of them is true.

Predication is either part of a Contradiction. Contradiction is an opposition of propositions which excludes any intermediate proposition. That part of a Contradiction which affirms one thing of another is Affirmation, that which denies one thing of another is Negation.

I apply the name Thesis to an immediate syllogistic principle which cannot be proved, and the previous possession of which is a necessary condition for learning something, but not all. That which is an indispensable antecedent to the acquisition of any knowledge I call an Axiom; for there are some principles of this kind, and ‘axiom’ is the name generally applied to them.

A Thesis which embodies one or other part of a predication (that is that the subject does, or does not, exist) is a Hypothesis; one which makes no such assertion a Definition. Definition is really a kind of Thesis; e.g. the arithmetician ‘lays it down’ that Unity is indivisibility in respect to quantity, but this is not a Hypothesis, for the nature of unity and the fact of its existence are not one and the same question.

Since then belief and knowledge with regard to any subject result from the possession of a demonstrative syllogism, and since a syllogism is demonstrative when the principles from which it is drawn are true, we must not merely have a previous knowledge of some or all of these primary principles, but have a higher knowledge of them than of the conclusion.

The Cause always possesses the quality which it impresses on a subject in a higher degree than that subject; thus, that for which we love anything is dear in a higher degree than the actual object of our love. Hence if our knowledge and belief is due to its primary principles, we have a higher knowledge of these latter and believe more firmly in them, because the thing itself is a consequence of them. Now it is not possible to believe less in what one knows than in what one neither knows nor has attained to by some higher faculty than knowledge. But this will happen unless he whose belief is produced by demonstration has a previous knowledge of the primary principles, for it is more needful to believe in these principles, either all or some, than in the conclusion to which they lead.

Now in order to attain to that knowledge which comes by demonstration one must not only be better acquainted with and believe more firmly in the elementary principles than in the conclusion, but nothing must be better known nor more firmly believed in than the opposites of those principles from which a false conclusion contrary to the science itself can be educed; that is to say if he who possesses absolute knowledge is to be quite immovable in his opinions.