Democracy and Dictatorship - Norberto Bobbio - E-Book

Democracy and Dictatorship E-Book

Norberto Bobbio

0,0
18,99 €

-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

In this important volume Norberto Bobbio examines some of the central themes of political theory and presents a systematic exposition of his views. With great astuteness and profound scholarship, Bobbio unfolds the elements for a general theory of politics. Bobbio's wide-ranging argument is focused on four themes: the distinction between the public and the private; the concept of civil society; differing conceptions of the state and differing ways of understanding the legitimacy of state power; and the relation between Democracy and Dictatorship. Bobbio's discussion draws on a wealth of theoretical and historical material, from Plato, Aristotle, Hobbes and Locke to Marx, Weber, Habermas and Foucault. By analysing the development of different languages of politics in relation to changing social and historical contexts, Bobbio deepens our understanding of the concepts we use to describe and evaluate modern political systems.

Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:

Android
iOS
von Legimi
zertifizierten E-Readern

Seitenzahl: 345

Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



Table of Contents

Cover

Title

Copyright

Introduction: Democracy and the Decline of the Left

Preface

1 The Great Dichotomy: Public/Private

A DICHOTOMOUS PAIR

CORRESPONDING DICHOTOMIES

THE EVALUATIVE USE OF THE GREAT DICHOTOMY

THE SECOND MEANING OF THE DICHOTOMY

2 Civil Society

THE VARIOUS MEANINGS

THE MARXIAN INTERPRETATION

THE HEGELIAN SYSTEM

THE NATURAL LAW TRADITION

CIVIL SOCIETY AS CIVILIZED SOCIETY

THE CURRENT DEBATE

3 State, Power and Government

TOWARDS THE STUDY OF THE STATE

THE NAME AND THE THING

THE STATE AND POWER

THE FOUNDATION OF POWER

STATE AND LAW

THE FORMS OF GOVERNMENT

FORMS OF STATE

THE END OF THE STATE

4 Democracy and Dictatorship

DEMOCRACY IN THE THEORY OF GOVERNMENTAL FORMS

THE DESCRIPTIVE USE

THE EVALUATIVE USE

THE HISTORICAL USE

MODERN DEMOCRACY

REPRESENTATIVE DEMOCRACY AND DIRECT DEMOCRACY

POLITICAL DEMOCRACY AND SOCIAL DEMOCRACY

FORMAL DEMOCRACY AND SUBSTANTIVE DEMOCRACY

ANCIENT DICTATORSHIP

MODERN DICTATORSHIP

REVOLUTIONARY DICTATORSHIP

Bibliography

Index

End User License Agreement

Landmarks

Cover

Table of Contents

Begin Reading

Pages

C1

iii

iv

v

vii

viii

ix

x

xi

xii

xiii

xiv

xv

xvi

xvii

xviii

xix

xx

xxi

xxii

xxiii

xxiv

xxv

xxvi

xxvii

xxviii

xxix

xxx

1

2

3

4

5

6

7

8

9

10

11

12

13

14

15

16

17

18

19

20

21

22

23

24

25

26

27

28

29

30

31

32

33

34

35

36

37

38

39

40

41

42

43

44

45

46

47

48

49

50

51

52

53

54

55

56

57

58

59

60

61

62

63

64

65

66

67

68

69

70

71

72

73

74

75

76

77

78

79

80

81

82

83

84

85

86

87

88

89

90

91

92

93

94

95

96

97

98

99

100

101

102

103

104

105

106

107

108

109

110

111

112

113

114

115

116

117

118

119

120

121

122

123

124

125

126

127

128

129

130

131

132

133

134

136

137

138

139

140

141

142

143

144

145

146

147

148

149

150

151

152

153

154

155

156

157

158

159

160

161

162

163

164

165

166

167

168

169

170

171

172

173

174

175

176

177

178

179

180

181

182

183

184

185

186

e1

Democracy and Dictatorship

The Nature and Limits of State Power

NORBERTO BOBBIO

Translated by Peter Kennealy

English translation copyright © Polity Press 1989

First published as Stato, govemo, societa:Per una teoriageneraledella po/itica copyright © 1980, 1981, 1978 and, in the collection, copyright © 1985 Guilio Einaudi editore s.p.a., Torino

This translation first published 1989 by Polity Press in association with Blackwell Publishers Ltd. First published in paperback 1997.

Reprinted 2006

Polity Press65 Bridge StreetCambridge CB2 1UR, UK

Polity Press350 Main StreetMalden, MA 02148, USA

All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher.

Except in the United States of America, this book is sold subject to the condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re-sold, hired out, or otherwise circulated without the publisher’s prior consent in any form of binding or cover other than that in which it is published and without a similar condition including this condition being imposed on the subsequent purchaser.

ISBN 0–7456–0394-7ISBN 0–7456–1912–6 (pbk)

A CIP catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

For further information on Polity, visit our website: www.polity.co.uk

Introduction: Democracy and the Decline of the Left

byJohn Keane

THE DECLINE OF THE LEFT

What does it mean to be on the Left today? Few questions are so theoretically and politically significant – and so utterly perplexing. Only the origins of the term ‘Left’ seem uncontroversial.

It is well known that the idea of the Left is a child of the French Revolution – a metaphorical extension of the seating plan of the 1789 French Estates General, which became divided by the heated debates on the royal veto, with the ‘third Estate’ sitting to the King’s left and the nobility to his right. It is also common knowledge that the idea of the Left played a critical role in nineteenth-century politics. It heightened the perception of the body politic as a broken continuum, as permanently divided by competing attitudes towards social change and political order. In opposition to the foot-dragging conservatism of the Right, with its haughty belief in the need for strict order and social control, Leftists were progressives. They optimistically embraced a faith in science, rationality and industry. They proclaimed their love of liberty and equality, and appealed to the essential goodness and sociability of human nature. The Left sympathized with the downtrodden. It despised the rich and powerful. It denounced parliamentary democracy as a bourgeois institution. It battled for a world freed from the evils of capitalism, material scarcity and unhappiness.

Since the First World War, this classical image of the Left has been crumbling slowly. The Left has become more cautious about modernity. It is less magnetized by the myths of scientific-technical progress and, especially within its green fringes, it has become openly hostile to industrialism; by contrast, it is the Right, from Mussolini to Thatcher, which has abandoned its former nostalgia and circumspection, and pressed home revolutionary or reformist policies based on a deep faith in scientific and economic modernization. In the same period, the levelling image of the Left has been damaged badly by its association with the cruel Stalinist programme of destroying liberty, equality and solidarity by means of cunning, violence, blood and terror – in Spain, in the Moscow trials, the Hitler – Stalin pact, Katyn and the military invasions of Hungary and Czechoslovakia. In consequence, the Left has become widely identified with the mastery of the skills of the lion and the fox, with the passion for political power and the wholesale politicization of personal and social life.

The Left’s founding image of international class solidarity and opposition to state violence has also taken a severe beating. The rise of national communist regimes (as in Yugoslavia, China and Vietnam) has demonstrated that Leftism is not synonymous with selfless internationalism. Severe tensions among these regimes – the Maoist denunciation of Soviet ‘revisionism’ as a right-wing betrayal of communism is a dramatic case in point – and the more recent outbreak of war between these states (as in Indochina) have served to reinforce the image of the Left as a purveyor of self-interested power politics – as a mirror image of its right-wing opponents.

In recent years, the meaning of the term ‘Left’ has fallen into deeper disarray, especially in the countries of the West. It has become a muddled label which often obscures more than it clarifies. The appearance of the New Left at the end of the 1950s is one source of this trend. The willingness of many Left governments and parties after 1945 to embrace the ‘mixed economy’ and their more recent fascination with market mechanisms, the profit motive and small business has further blurred its distinctively ‘left’ qualities. Matters have been worsened by the confused reaction of trade unions, once considered the ‘natural’ heartland of Left support, to the failure of Keynesian reflationary policies. This confusion has been multiplied by deindustrialization, the growth of a new underclass and the emergence of more ‘flexible’ technologies, production methods and consumer styles. The western Left’s loss of direction can also be traced to its nostalgic defence of centralized state bureaucracy and outdated techniques of management and planning. The conventional belief on the Left that state planning and fixing of markets plus selective nationalization plus spending money equals socialism has come unstuck. And the consequent tendency of some parts of the Left to display more pride in the past than faith in the future has been exacerbated by its intellectual torpor – its bad habit of submitting to the hypnotic powers of the Right, of repeating clichés and making politics through conventional labels.

The writings of Norberto Bobbio, Italy’s leading political thinker, are an important reaction to this deep impasse of the Left. His work is pathbreaking because he sees the demand for more democracy as the key to a successful redefinition of the Left. What does democracy mean in this context? Bobbio’s unusual ‘liberal socialist’ understanding of the term has been shaped by his early experiences in the liberal intellectual milieu of Turin in the 1930s, his deep involvement in the anti-Fascist Resistance, his subsequent intellectual and journalistic dialogues with the Italian Left, especially the PCI, and his current role as Life Senator and independent franc-tireur within Italian parliamentary politics.1 Against the backdrop of such experiences, Bobbio insists – in the face of its twentieth-century vulgarization that the concept of democracy is not elastic. It is not a word which can be made to mean whatever we choose it to mean. Democracy is understood by him as a system of procedural rules which specify who is authorized to make collective decisions and through which procedures such decisions are to be made. In contrast to all forms of heteronomous government, democracy comprises procedures for arriving at collective decisions in a way which secures the fullest possible participation of interested parties. At a minimum, according to Bobbio, democratic procedures include equal and universal adult suffrage; majority rule and guarantees of minority rights, which ensure that collective decisions are approved by a substantial number of those expected to make them; the rule of law; and constitutional guarantees of freedom of assembly and expression and other liberties, which help guarantee that those expected to decide or to elect those who decide can choose among real alternatives.

Democracy in this sense is a method of preventing those who govern from permanently appropriating power for their own ends. Those exercising power are subject to procedures which enable others to question, rotate or sack them. The distribution of power in democratic systems tends to reflect the outcomes of political contests framed by permanent decision-making rules. Conflict and compromise are therefore institutionalized, and power becomes secular and ‘disembodied’. It is not permanently consubstantial with any particular individual or group – a monarch, for instance – but is exercised instead by flesh-and-blood mortals who are subject to removal and are accountable to others, in accordance with the rules of the democratic game.

Bobbio argues that in general the present-day Left has either muddled or no clear ideas about the importance and nature of the rules of democracy, and in particular whether to reform or replace them. This leads him to challenge several standard Leftist misconceptions about democracy. For example, Bobbio is adamant that the historical emergence of liberal democratic institutions, such as free elections, competitive party systems and written constitutions, represented a great leap forward in the fight for more democracy. Liberal democratic institutions are not necessarily a device for protecting the class interests of the bourgeoisie. Liberal democracy (to paraphrase Lenin) is not the best political shell for capitalism. Liberal democratic institutions are in fact an indispensable bulwark against the unending arrogance of political actors, a vital mechanism for limiting the scope and haughtiness of state power. A post-liberal democracy is thinkable and desirable, but a non-liberal democracy is a contradiction in terms and in fact.

Bobbio is also adamant that the friends of democracy must reject the bad ‘New Left’ habit of calling for the disappearance of all organization and its replacement by so-called spontaneous action. A democratic polity without procedural rules is not only a contradiction in terms. It is also a recipe for arbitrary decision making and misgovernment. The friends of democracy must also recognize that the full replacement of representative forms of democracy by participatory, direct democracy – which require (in the case of decisions affecting the whole polity) the public assembly of millions of citizens – is technically impossible in large-scale, complex societies. Direct democracy, the participation of citizens in the agora, is suited only to small states and organizatons in which ‘the people find it easy to meet and in which every citizen can easily get to know all the others’ (Rousseau). More controversially, Bobbio argues that the attempt to foist the principle of direct democracy on to representative institutions – for instance, applying a binding mandate to elected parliamentary ‘delegates’ – is undesirable, since it contradicts the principle, indispensable in any parliamentary democracy, that representatives represent general rather than narrowly sectional interests and therefore require some powers to negotiate freely and to act independently of those whom they represent.

Bobbio emphasizes the important point that direct democracy thrives upon consensual decision-making, and that it therefore works best when there are a limited number of alternative policy choices – nuclear power or no nuclear power, peace or war, or the legalization or criminalization of abortion. Otherwise, the trust, patience and mutual support that are required within self-governing circles are often overburdened with multiple and conflicting points of view, the tensions among which cannot be resolved easily without the presence of intermediaries – that is, without institutions of delegated or representative democracy which . ‘filter out’ and simplify the kaleidoscope of conflicting opinions.

This is not to say that representative, parliamentary democracy is the alpha and omega of political forms. Bobbio recognizes, correctly, that the representative system is constrained and limited by accumulations of social power within civil society. The vast majority of citizens has no say in major decisions concerning economic investment, production and growth. Churches, trade unions and many other institutions of civil society remain insufficiently democratic. Exactly how more democracy within the sphere of civil society might be achieved in practice is unclear from Bobbio’s account. He refers only to the need to develop, broaden and reinforce all the institutions from which modern democracy was born. Priority should be given, in his view, to the task of supplementing political democracy with ‘social democracy’ – extending the process of democratization from the political sphere (where individuals are regarded as citizens) to the civil sphere, where individuals are regarded variously as men and women, entrepreneurs and workers, teachers and students, producers and consumers. Struggles over where citizens can vote should be given as much priority as the struggles in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries over who can vote.

Bobbio emphasizes that in practice this refinement and extension of democracy – broadening the domains where citizens can vote – does not require all individuals to play the role of fulltime political animals. Too much democracy can kill off democracy. The wholesale politicization of life, the attempt to create a society of fulltime, omnicompetent citizens, is in fact antithetical to democracy. It would produce hellish and unworkable results – everything would be defined as political, private life would be swallowed up by the public sphere, human beings would be transformed, perhaps forcibly, into ‘total citizens’, despite the fact that the growing diversification and complexity of modern societies prevents individual citizens from being in the same place at the same time to make decisions which affect their lives directly or indirectly. Free time would become a thing of the past. The life of the fulltime, omnicompetent citizen would be a nightmare of interminable meetings, endless negotiations and late-night telephone calls. Moreover, according to Bobbio, Europeans are heirs of an historical tradition in which state power is supposed to be limited in favour of non-state spheres, such as religious communities, households, centres of learning and research, and markets.

This historically felt need to limit the scope and power of the state is a central and distinctive feature of Bobbio’s attempt to redefine the meaning of Left politics. He views state power as necessary and yet corruptible and dangerous, and as therefore in need of preventive measures and effective defences, such as a plurality of social forces and organizations which run parallel to the state. In Bobbio’s view, the enormous problem which faces the Left is to know how to create through its own agency a state apparatus which is efficient without being oppressive or, in other words, which can function effectively as the agent of civil society without at the same time lapsing into a dictatorship.

THE GREAT DICHOTOMIES

This volume of connected essays – a small encyclopaedia of key political terms – is jam-packed with insights which bear on this problem. Consistent with Bobbio’s dislike of obscure jargon and emotive slogans – his intellectual temperament is consistently sceptical and democratic and imbued with a sense of the complexity of things – these essays get down to the serious business of carefully analysing classical, medieval and modern traditions of reflection on the scope and limits of political action. The essays might be described as an exercise in historical semantics – as an attempt to reconstruct the changing meaning through time of certain political keywords. This exercise is evidently infinite in scope. There are always new texts to be read and further illustrations to be developed, and both tasks would in turn modify or amplify the conclusions already reached. Bobbio meets this possible objection by concentrating on a number of key political terms and their opposites – such as the public and the private, civil society and the state, democracy and dictatorship – which hold the key to resolving the problem of how to limit and control the exercise of state power. His choice of certain pairs of concepts (’great dichotomies’ Bobbio calls them) reveals his deep attachment to the tradition of modern liberal constitutionalism, but it is no less unusual and stimulating for that. It has the advantage of illuminating the origins, shifting meanings and normative implications of each term by comparing it with its partner. In this way, the structure of any given political system or historical era can be better understood by knowing what has been said or written about it. For example, the differentia specifica of modern times and its patterns of political thought when compared to its classical and medieval counterparts can be better grasped, and the rough and narrow paths of democratic theory can be better negotiated.

The essays assembled in this volume are invaluable guides in this adventure. To begin with, Bobbio examines the public/private dichotomy. This contrast first entered the history of western political thought for the purpose of distinguishing between what belongs to a group as a collectivity and what belongs to its single members or lesser groupings .like households and enterprises. The public/private dichotomy in turn harbours other important distinctions, which Bobbio teases out with skill and patience: for example, the distinction between associations of equals (as in the polis) and communities of unequals (as in the oikos); between the public law which is imposed by political authority and the private law which regulates the interaction of private persons in such matters as property, inheritance and marriage; and the distinction between the principles of distributive justice, which guide public authority in the distribution of honours and duties, and the principles of commutative justice, which cover buying and selling, labour contracts and other private individuals and groups considered to be of equal value.

Bobbio points out that the original distinction between the public and the private was ordered hierarchically, in that the public was affirmed as supreme in relation to the peripheral powers of the private. An example is the classic definition of Cicero of the res publica as an aggregation of people bonded together by the utilitas communione. This primacy of the public over the private was challenged successively, for example, by the diffusion of Roman law, whose principal institutions are property, contracts and the family. This trend was reinforced, ironically, by the development (by Bartolo di Sassoferrato, Jean Bodin and others) of a systematic body of public law during the first phases of development of the modern state. This hastened the questioning of the primacy of the public over the private by triggering disputes about whether the people have forever conceded or only temporarily entrusted power to the sovereign. During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries the opposition of the private sphere to the public underwent a thorough ‘modernization’. Locke and others argued for the inviolability of property in the lives, liberties and other natural rights of individuals. Even theorists of absolutism like Hobbes considered as unjust the sovereign who violated the property of his or her subjects. And prior to the French Revolution the exponents of political economy radically extended this liberal theory of the primacy of the private over the public. They emphasized the fundamental difference between the sphere of economic relations (understood as an ensemble of relationships among formally equal individuals who are in fact rendered unequal by the division of labour) and the sphere of political institutions – a distinction which powerfully reinforced the defence of civil society against the state during that period.

The ‘great dichotomy’ between civil society and the state features prominently in this volume. In today’s political vocabulary, Bobbio points out, civil society refers to the sphere of social relations – households, communications media, markets, churches, voluntary organizations and social movements – which are not controlled directly by state institutions. It is widely understood as a defining characteristic of modern life. Civil society and the state are seen as two necessarily separate but contiguous and interdependent aspects of contemporary life. Bobbio emphasizes the novelty of this viewpoint. Well into the eighteenth century, European political thinkers understood civil society as a synonym for a type of political association whose members are subject to laws which ensure peaceful order and good government. This meaning of the term is traceable through Cicero’s idea of societas civilis to the Aristotelean view that civil society (koionia politike) is that society, the polis, which contains and governs all others. According to Bobbio, this old custom of treating civil society as coterminous with the state was always under pressure from attempts, recurrent in Christian thought, to distinguish the area of competence of the civil powers from the domain of religious power. It was challenged directly for the first time by German writers (especially Marx and Hegel). For Hegel civil society is a moment in the process of the formation and completion of the State. It includes the market economy, social classes, corporations, and institutions whose transactions are regulated by civil law and, as such, are not directly dependent upon the political state itself. Marx’s interpretation of Hegel’s concept of civil society is by contrast reductive and ultimately distorted, in Bobbio’s view Marx’s bürgerliche Gesellschaft referred to society in the sense of a class society riddled with bourgeois practices and assumptions. It is a product of an historical subject, the bourgeoisie, which legitimated its struggles against the absolutist state in the language of the rights of man and citizen, which in reality serves only the particular interests of the bourgeoisie.

Bobbio’s treatment of the original and subsequent accounts of modern civil society – including that of Gramsci – arguably places too much emphasis on the German case and neglects the reticence of German thinkers about its democratic implications.2 Bobbio nevertheless correctly underscores the wide range of conflicting meanings of the expression ‘civil society’ and its counterpart, the state. Bobbio shows that state institutions have often been viewed from a variety of standpoints. They can be treated as an aspect of the history of institutions or treated in terms of the history of political ideas or of normative political philosophy. The theme of the state can also be approached through the distinction between sociological and legal doctrines (a distinction emphasized in Georg Jellinek’s General Doctrineof the State(Allgemeine Staatslehre) 1910); that is, the state can be viewed either as primarily a legally produced and legally governed entity or as a form of organization which cannot be dissociated from the ensemble of underlying social relations which condition or determine its functioning.

The historical appearance of the idea of the state in its modern form is attributed by Bobbio to such works as Machiavelli’s Prince and Hobbes’s Leviathan, where the state is understood as the supreme institutionalized power – the ‘machine state’ – that can be exercised over the inhabitants of a given territory. The state is defined as the bearer of the summapotestas; whoever has the exclusive power or right to use force on a given territory is considered sovereign. Whether this idea of the state – in contrast to the idea of the Greek polis and the Roman res publica – was entirely novel is a matter of deep controversy. According to Bobbio, some writers – Max Weber is among the most important – see the reality of the modern state, with its monopoly of the means of violence, administration and taxation, as unprecedented. Other writers – Machiavelli’s close reading of Roman history in search of political examples applicable to the states of his time is an example – have been inclined to identify a measure of continuity between the systems of the ancient, medieval and modern worlds.

Theories of the state have also been marked by bitter controversies about the appropriate relationship between sovereign and subjects, rulers and ruled, the state and its citizens. This relationship has been defined by most political thinkers as a relationship between superiors and inferiors. The history of political thought, Bobbio’s analysis shows, has been mainly a history written from above. The dominant tradition that runs from Plato’s Statesman and Xenophon’s Cyropaedia to Hobbes’s Leviathan and Schmitt’s DieDiktatur has represented political power from the standpoint of the rulers. It has sought to justify the power-holders’ right to command and the subjects’ duty to obey by defending various principles of legitimacy. These include the authority of God; the will of the people; nature (as an original force, kratos, or as the law of reason or modern natural law); appeals to history; or, as in legal positivism, references to the fact that law is made and enforced by authorities appointed by the political system itself. This dominant tradition has come under fire increasingly in modern times. The entitlements of the governed – the ‘hidden side of the moon’ of western political thought in Bobbio’s words – have come ever more sharply in focus. The natural rights of the individual; the liberty, wealth and happiness of citizens; the right of resistance to unjust laws; the separation of powers; the rule of law; office-holding and law-making subject to time limits: these and other principles have been invoked in opposition to state-centred theories of politics. Such principles are seen to exist independently of political power, which is required both to respect and to protect them. The individual is not seen to be destined to serve the state. Rather, the state must serve the individual so that, as Spinoza put it, even sovereigns who can do anything they want are forced in practice to recognize that they cannot make a table eat grass.

The changing fortunes of the theory of dictatorship, analysed in the last essay in this volume, is an important example of the way in which the entitlements of the governed becomes an ever more prominent theme in modern political thought. From ancient to early modern thinkers (up to Rousseau, Babeuf and Buonarrotti) the institution of dictatorship was distinguished by its exceptional and temporary character. ‘Dictator’ was originally the name of the Roman magistrate to whom extraordinary powers were legitimately given in times of war or domestic revolt. Bobbio points out that the idea that dictatorship is required periodically to stabilize an existing order comes under heavy fire in modern times. In this era of great revolutionary upheavals, the concept of dictatorship is extended to include regimes which aim to change the world, to smash the old order, and to establish a brand new regime. The modern idea of dictatorship – Buonarrotti’s committee of ‘wise and enlightened’ men who boldly guide the revolution is an example – is further distinguished from its classical counterpart by the insistence that not only the powers of the executive but all state functions should be mobilized in support of dictatorship. During the nineteenth century, the originally positive connotations of the term dictatorship were also dissolved. Marx, Engels and others considered every state to be dictatorial. Dictatorship was denounced as ‘domination’, as a necessary and enduring feature of the exercise of all forms of political power. According to Bobbio, this shift away from a positive to a negative definition of dictatorship is even more marked during the twentieth century. From the time of the fiery debates about the nature of the Bolshevik and fascist regimes, dictatorship and democracy are seen to be antithetical forms of government. Dictatorship is widely regarded with suspicion or disdain. It comes to mean all undemocratic ways of wielding power.

Although Bobbio notes – approvingly – that democracy is today still generally reckoned to be preferable to dictatorship, he is not starry-eyed about its merits and advantages. Certainly, he considers democracy the chief antidote of dictatorship and violent politics, which are potentially inherent in the operation of all modern states. In the final analysis, these states rest on a foundation of armed force. This means not only that the danger of war and the militarization of civil society is omnipresent in the field of inter-state relations, but also that the political leaders of each nation-state continually have access to its irreducibly violent potential. Whenever they are challenged or wish to accumulate further power, political leaders can resort to institutions such as the police and the military, which are deeply antithetical to democracy because they thrive on secrecy, cunning, enforced unanimity and, ultimately’ the shout to arms and the crash of hobnailed boots on the pavement.

By contrast, democratic procedures are based on nonviolent, open negotiations and revocable compromises, and for this reason Bobbio considers them more ‘civilized’. Yet his enthusiasm for democracy is controlled. It does not treat democracy as a synonym for the ‘good life’ (Lipset). A unique feature of Bobbio’s defence of democracy is its honest concern with the limits of democracy. He emphasizes several of these limits. While the democratic method is treated as a precious and vital human invention, he insists that it is not always and everywhere a viable mode of decision-making. Bobbio does not repeat the oldest (and old hat) arguments against democracy, for instance that democracy always degenerates into lawlessness and licence, so that the father fears his son and ‘the master fears and flatters his pupils and the pupils laugh at their masters and teachers’ (Plato). Bobbio instead illustrates his thesis about the limits of democracy with reference to periods of crisis, such as war, violent upheaval and domestic ‘states of emergency’, in which democratic rules of the game rarely apply. (Whether they can or should be made to apply is a different problem, left untreated by Bobbio.) In such periods, social and political outcomes are determined by self-interested calculation and bloody struggles for power over others. The basic rules of democracy seem to be an unaffordable luxury.

Bobbio also sees the democratic method to be threatened by a number of irreversible historical trends. For example, the extension of the suffrage and the growth of social demands on the liberal democratic state have forced it to expand its functions and services and – the Weberian roots of Bobbio’s argument are here strongly evident – to administer these services through a constantly expanding bureaucratic apparatus which is structured hierarchically and not democratically. Bobbio further claims that the number of problems requiring technical expertise and professional solutions is rising, and that this reduces the applicability of the democratic principle that everyone can decide everything. Inevitably, government by technicians spreads. Citizens’ (potential) sovereignty is whittled away in favour of qualunquismo, the apathy and indifference of private beings who are interested only in cultivating their gardens. Finally, Bobbio laments the undemocratic and atomizing impact of the mass media. He points out that democracy presupposes the free and full development of the faculties of individual citizens, and yet he claims that this requirement is violated daily by the manipulative appeals of the press and broadcasting media, which diminish the space reserved for informed judgements by stimulating convictions based on either fleeting emotions or the passive imitation of others – all in the name of ‘popular choice’. The abstract principle of popular sovereignty is thereby translated into reality in debased form.

Bobbio’s account of the limits of democracy is arguably incomplete and less than convincing. There is much evidence that the ‘irreversible’ historical trends alleged by Bobbio are in fact highly contingent developments. Bureaucratic organizations certainly tend to reduce their members and clients to mere objects of administrative control, but they also typically stimulate the growth of independent public spheres by depending on a measure of initiative from their members and by feigning acceptance of the principle of mediating conflicting interests through controversy, open discussion, compromise and consensus. Bobbio’s defence of the principle of government by technicians is also questionable. Complex organizations cannot operate automatically, that is, guided only by technical knowledge and procedures. Human skill, improvisation and collective judgements are essential for preventing them from regularly malfunctioning in unexpected and often dangerous ways. The introduction of the most advanced machine systems (such as computers and robots) into complex organizations further increases the number of open-ended and unstructured problems, which cannot be solved by technical expertise alone but only with the co-operation of those who work directly with these new information technologies. And the astonishing capacity of these technologies to alter flexibly both the range of products and rhythms of work can be managed only through collective human decisions at the point of production. Finally, the emphasis placed by Bobbio on the atomizing and depoliticizing effects of the mass media is one-sided. It neglects the serious political controversies which have erupted in recent decades between the supporters of state-regulated and market-regulated press and audio-visual media; and it neglects the ways in which most citizens – as the remarkable growth of video piracy and the illegal use of descramblers suggest – today retain a native (if undeveloped) capacity to select, reinterpret, criticize, or – like tortoises – shield themselves completely against the appeals of the mass media.3