Is Self-Determination a Dangerous Illusion? - David Miller - E-Book

Is Self-Determination a Dangerous Illusion? E-Book

David Miller

0,0
10,99 €

-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

Claims to self-determination are rife in world politics today. They range from Scottish and Catalonian campaigns for independence to calls for the devolution of power to regions and cities. But is self-determination meaningful or desirable in the twenty-first century, or merely a dangerous illusion? In this book, David Miller mounts a powerful defence of political self-determination. He explains why it is valuable and argues that geographic proximity alone is not enough for groups to have the capacity for self-determination: group members must also identify with each other. He explores the different political forms that self-determination can take, and he suggests some realistic constraints on how it can be achieved, concluding that people exercising their collective agency is still both feasible and important. Anyone concerned by the theoretical issues raised by the various secessionist and nationalist movements around the world should read this book.

Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:

Android
iOS
von Legimi
zertifizierten E-Readern

Seitenzahl: 134

Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



Contents

Series title

Title page

Copyright page

Acknowledgements

1 Introduction

Notes

2 The Value of Self-Determination

Notes

3 The Agents of Self-Determination

Notes

4 Self-Determination and Secession

Notes

5 Self-Determination Within, Alongside and Beyond the Nation-State?

Notes

End User License Agreement

Guide

Cover

Contents

1 Introduction

Pages

ii

iii

iv

vii

viii

1

2

3

4

5

6

7

8

9

10

11

12

13

14

15

16

17

18

19

20

21

22

23

24

117

118

119

25

26

27

28

29

30

31

32

33

34

35

36

37

38

39

40

41

42

43

44

45

46

47

120

121

48

49

50

51

52

53

54

55

56

57

58

59

60

61

62

63

64

65

66

67

68

69

70

122

123

71

72

73

74

75

76

77

78

79

80

81

82

83

84

85

86

87

88

89

90

91

92

93

124

125

94

95

96

97

98

99

100

101

102

103

104

105

106

107

108

109

110

111

112

113

114

115

116

126

127

Series title

Political Theory Today

Janna Thompson,

Should Current Generations Make Reparations for Slavery?

Chris Bertram,

Do States Have the Right to Exclude Immigrants?

Diana Coole,

Should We Control World Population?

Christopher Finlay,

Is Just War Possible?

George Klosko,

Why Should We Obey the Law?

Emanuela Ceva & Michele Bocchiola,

Is Whistleblowing a Duty?

Elizabeth Frazer & Kimberly Hutchings,

Can Political Violence Ever Be Justified?

Margaret Moore,

Who Should Own Natural Resources?

David Miller,

Is Self-Determination a Dangerous Illusion?

Is Self-Determination a Dangerous Illusion?

David Miller

polity

Copyright page

Copyright © David Miller 2020

The right of David Miller to be identified as Author of this Work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.

First published in 2020 by Polity Press

Polity Press

65 Bridge Street

Cambridge CB2 1UR, UK

Polity Press

101 Station Landing

Suite 300

Medford, MA 02155, USA

All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purpose of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher.

ISBN-13: 978-1-5095-3346-6

ISBN-13: 978-1-5095-3347-3 (pb)

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.

Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

Names: Miller, David, 1946- author.

Title: Is self-determination a dangerous illusion? / David Miller.

Description: Medford, MA : Polity, 2019. | Series: Political theory today

Identifiers: LCCN 2019014896 (print) | LCCN 2019981425 (ebook) | ISBN 9781509533466 (hardback) | ISBN 9781509533473 (pbk.) | ISBN 9781509533497 (ebook)

Subjects: LCSH: Self-determination, National.

Classification: LCC KZ1269 .M55 2019 (print) | LCC KZ1269 (ebook) | DDC 341.26--dc23

LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2019014896

LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2019981425

Typeset in 11 on 15 Sabon

by Fakenham Prepress Solutions, Fakenham, Norfolk NR21 8NL

Printed and bound in the UK by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon

The publisher has used its best endeavours to ensure that the URLs for external websites referred to in this book are correct and active at the time of going to press. However, the publisher has no responsibility for the websites and can make no guarantee that a site will remain live or that the content is or will remain appropriate.

Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been overlooked the publisher will be pleased to include any necessary credits in any subsequent reprint or edition.

For further information on Polity, visit our website: politybooks.com

Acknowledgements

This book was written in the delightful surroundings of the Institute for Futures Studies in Stockholm, where visitors have no specific obligations other than to meet occasionally for fika to consume coffee and kanelbullar. I should like to thank Gustaf Arrhenius, Ludvig Beckman and the staff of the Institute for the support they provided, and for stimulating conversations on topics more or less closely related to self-determination. Material from the book was presented there and also to political theory workshops at Uppsala University and Nuffield College, Oxford: I am very grateful to everyone who offered comments and made suggestions at those meetings. Thanks are due, too, to George Owers and three readers for Polity Press for providing detailed comments on the manuscript, in the process saving me from a number of faux pas. Last but not least, Margaret has been a constant source of advice and encouragement.

1Introduction

In 1976, the United Nations re-affirmed its commitment to human rights in two major documents, the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights. Both contained, as Article 1, the following sentences: ‘All peoples have the right of self-determination. By virtue of that right they freely determine their political status and freely pursue their economic, social and cultural development.’

The presence of this Article is puzzling in several respects. It seems out of place in documents devoted to setting out a long list of individual human rights since the right it proclaims is clearly a collective right, a right belonging to peoples, plural, not to individual persons, as the Article’s wording makes plain. During the long period in which the Covenants were being drafted, several western governments had opposed its inclusion, no doubt foreseeing the implications it would have for their remaining colonial possessions. Then there is the initially surprising fact that no attempt is made to clarify the term ‘people’. If ‘people’ isn’t just another word for ‘state’, who counts as one and who doesn’t? Nor does the Article explain what self-determination involves. The second sentence suggests two things: that a ‘people’ should decide on how it wants to organize itself politically, such as by having its own independent state; and that it should then set its own domestic policy goals. But the Article does not require that it must adopt a democratic form of government. As we shall see later, self-determination and democracy, though they are related, are not the same. By placing self-determination at the head of a long list of human rights, the Covenants imply that a people is being seriously wronged if denied the right to govern itself but give us little clue as to what following Article 1 might mean in practice.

International lawyers have struggled to clarify this alleged right of self-determination. A narrow interpretation would say that it is simply intended to protect established states from external interference. In other words, a ‘people’ is indeed nothing more or less than a state. But in practice it has been interpreted more widely than this so as to apply in two main cases where newly independent states are being created. One of these is decolonization of the kind that occurred in the 1960s and 1970s, when European states were forced to relinquish their possessions in Africa and Asia. In this context, the inhabitants of former colonies were treated as separate ‘peoples’ with a right to break free from their colonial masters and found independent states. The other is the collapse of large conglomerates, such as occurred at the end of the First World War when the Habsburg and Ottoman Empires were dissolved. Here, new states, such as Poland and Czechoslovakia, were created in order to grant self-government to nations who had been submerged in the former empires but were now given the right to control their own destinies.1

This indeed was the moment at which the idea of self-determination first sprang to prominence. It was supported for different reasons by the Bolsheviks under Lenin’s leadership and by US President Woodrow Wilson, who played a large part in redrawing the map of Europe in an attempt to ensure that state borders and national borders would henceforth coincide. Wilson announced as his fundamental principle:

that the countries of the world belong to the people who live in them, and that they have a right to determine their own destiny and their own form of government and their own policy, and that no body of statesmen, sitting anywhere, no matter whether they represent the overwhelming physical force of the world or not, has the right to assign any great people to a sovereignty under which it does not care to live.2

But how could this bold claim be put into practice? It appears to assume that ‘countries’ are made up of people who, once given the chance, would all agree on how they wish to be governed, so the problem of self-determination could be solved by going and asking them the question directly. But what if, instead, we find that, in Europe and elsewhere, populations are interspersed in such a way that it is impossible to draw neat boundaries around them and say that we have found homogeneous ‘peoples’ who are then entitled, by Wilson’s principle, to choose their form of government? Then it seems that achieving self-determination for one nation will involve denying it to others, who might form a minority within the borders of one country, or be dispersed across two or more. Wilson’s Secretary of State, Robert Lansing, who was closely involved in the post-war peace negotiations, came to regard his master’s pronouncement with dismay:

The more I think about the President’s declaration as to the right of ‘self-determination’, the more convinced I am of the danger of putting such ideas into the minds of certain races. It is bound to be the basis of impossible demands on the Peace Congress and create trouble in many lands. . . . The phrase is simply loaded with dynamite. It will raise hopes which can never be realised. It will, I fear, cost thousands of lives. . . . What a calamity that the phrase was ever uttered! What misery it will cause!3

From the examples he offers, it appears that Lansing’s main concern was the encouragement that Wilson’s doctrine would offer to groups already struggling against their inclusion in colonial empires or large states, and so the violence that he anticipated would occur because the imperial powers would forcefully resist their demands. But Lansing worried too that some self-determination claims might simply be mutually incompatible. If the Boers were granted self-determination within South Africa, how could the other peoples of that region enjoy it too? Or if the Jews were to achieve self-determination in Palestine, as Wilson’s commitment to Zionism implied, what would become of the Arab inhabitants of that area? Lansing’s words were prophetic indeed; and they give us one very obvious sense in which self-determination might be a dangerous illusion. Proclaiming self-determination as a human right suggests that it is something that every human being can enjoy, like the right to food or bodily security. But what if the self-determination of some is always achieved at the expense of the self-determination of others?

The problem Lansing identified is not the only reason for thinking that self-determination might be a dangerous illusion – that by leading people to hope for something it may be impossible for them to achieve, it opens the door to resentment, political alienation and, in the worst case, violence. Although I will argue in this book in favour of the moral and political importance of self-determination, I want to take the case against it seriously as well. Let me add to Lansing’s criticism three more reasons for doubting that collective self-determination is a political goal worth pursuing.

The first takes us back to the silence of the International Covenants on the question of who counts as a people for purposes of self-determination. Is there any non-arbitrary way of deciding which groups should be given the right to govern themselves? To confine the right of self-determination to existing states is effectively to say that only those who have already achieved self-determination are entitled to exercise it. But this makes little sense, morally speaking. How could we justify saying that once the Estonians had their own state, they were entitled to be self-determining, but so long as they were part of the Soviet Union they were not? As we have already seen, international law, despite the fact that its principles tend to reflect the interests of established states, has also recognized self-determination rights in two main cases where groups did not already have their own states. But if we now compare these cases more closely, we see that their underlying logic is somewhat contradictory. In the aftermath of the First World War, when new independent states were being created, their boundaries were drawn broadly along national lines. For instance, a Polish state was created to grant self-determination to the Polish nation, a people united by ties of language, culture and religion, with a territorial heartland and a history of political independence that had rudely been brought to an end in 1795 when their state was partitioned between Austria, Prussia and Russia. So here the relevant ‘people’ was defined first, in terms of national identity, and then the territorial boundaries of their vehicle of self-determination – the state – were drawn so as to encase it geographically.

In the period of decolonization following the Second World War, by contrast, a very different logic was followed. The process was governed by the international legal principle of uti possidetis, which holds that where new state borders are being defined, they must follow existing lines of demarcation between administrative units.4 But, as many commentators have pointed out, colonial boundaries were created for different purposes and often as a result of mutually advantageous deals struck between the colonizers, so the areas they circumscribe were unlikely to be suitable as the territories of independent states. Indeed, internal boundary lines within colonies may have been drawn with the intention of keeping the colony intact by cutting across the territories traditionally held by different ethnic groups, but that became a source of problems once these smaller units became independent.5 The aftermath of decolonization left many ethnic groups in the position of national minorities who were denied their own rights of self-determination and, in consequence, very often many other rights as well. Colonial domination was replaced by domination by the majority ethnic group in the newly independent state.

In the earlier period and the European context, then, the ‘peoples’ who were considered ripe for self-determination were historic nations defined mainly in ethno-cultural terms; while in the later period and the post-colonial context, the relevant ‘peoples’ were those who lived within pre-existing administrative borders, regardless of their ethno-cultural affinities, or lack of them. The first way of understanding peoplehood might appear superior to the second because less arbitrary, but no one should imagine that the world is made up of neat, consolidated nations potentially able to live within boundaries drawn in such a way that everyone inside is a compatriot (even Iceland, potentially a good candidate, now contains nearly a tenth of its population who are not native-born Icelanders). Often we find that people with contrasting national identities are geographically interspersed over wide areas, so there is no way of drawing clean lines between national communities; or else we find smaller nations ‘nested’ inside larger ones, as the Scots and the Welsh are in Britain, and the Catalans and Basques are in Spain, and the question is whether the right of self-determination is held primarily by the encompassing group or