Euthydemus, Crito, Euthyphro
Euthydemus, Crito, Euthyphro EUTHYDEMUSINTRODUCTION.EUTHYDEMUSCRITOINTRODUCTIONCRITOEUTHYPHROINTRODUCTION.EUTHYPHROCopyright
Euthydemus, Crito, Euthyphro
Plato
EUTHYDEMUS
INTRODUCTION.
The Euthydemus, though apt to be regarded by us only as an
elaborate jest, has also a very serious purpose. It may fairly
claim to be the oldest treatise on logic; for that science
originates in the misunderstandings which necessarily accompany the
first efforts of speculation. Several of the fallacies which are
satirized in it reappear in the Sophistici Elenchi of Aristotle and
are retained at the end of our manuals of logic. But if the order
of history were followed, they should be placed not at the end but
at the beginning of them; for they belong to the age in which the
human mind was first making the attempt to distinguish thought from
sense, and to separate the universal from the particular or
individual. How to put together words or ideas, how to escape
ambiguities in the meaning of terms or in the structure of
propositions, how to resist the fixed impression of an 'eternal
being' or 'perpetual flux,' how to distinguish between words and
things—these were problems not easy of solution in the infancy of
philosophy. They presented the same kind of difficulty to the
half-educated man which spelling or arithmetic do to the mind of a
child. It was long before the new world of ideas which had been
sought after with such passionate yearning was set in order and
made ready for use. To us the fallacies which arise in the
pre-Socratic philosophy are trivial and obsolete because we are no
longer liable to fall into the errors which are expressed by them.
The intellectual world has become better assured to us, and we are
less likely to be imposed upon by illusions of words.The logic of Aristotle is for the most part latent in the
dialogues of Plato. The nature of definition is explained not by
rules but by examples in the Charmides, Lysis, Laches, Protagoras,
Meno, Euthyphro, Theaetetus, Gorgias, Republic; the nature of
division is likewise illustrated by examples in the Sophist and
Statesman; a scheme of categories is found in the Philebus; the
true doctrine of contradiction is taught, and the fallacy of
arguing in a circle is exposed in the Republic; the nature of
synthesis and analysis is graphically described in the Phaedrus;
the nature of words is analysed in the Cratylus; the form of the
syllogism is indicated in the genealogical trees of the Sophist and
Statesman; a true doctrine of predication and an analysis of the
sentence are given in the Sophist; the different meanings of one
and being are worked out in the Parmenides. Here we have most of
the important elements of logic, not yet systematized or reduced to
an art or science, but scattered up and down as they would
naturally occur in ordinary discourse. They are of little or no use
or significance to us; but because we have grown out of the need of
them we should not therefore despise them. They are still
interesting and instructive for the light which they shed on the
history of the human mind.There are indeed many old fallacies which linger among us,
and new ones are constantly springing up. But they are not of the
kind to which ancient logic can be usefully applied. The weapons of
common sense, not the analytics of Aristotle, are needed for their
overthrow. Nor is the use of the Aristotelian logic any longer
natural to us. We no longer put arguments into the form of
syllogisms like the schoolmen; the simple use of language has been,
happily, restored to us. Neither do we discuss the nature of the
proposition, nor extract hidden truths from the copula, nor dispute
any longer about nominalism and realism. We do not confuse the form
with the matter of knowledge, or invent laws of thought, or imagine
that any single science furnishes a principle of reasoning to all
the rest. Neither do we require categories or heads of argument to
be invented for our use. Those who have no knowledge of logic, like
some of our great physical philosophers, seem to be quite as good
reasoners as those who have. Most of the ancient puzzles have been
settled on the basis of usage and common sense; there is no need to
reopen them. No science should raise problems or invent forms of
thought which add nothing to knowledge and are of no use in
assisting the acquisition of it. This seems to be the natural limit
of logic and metaphysics; if they give us a more comprehensive or a
more definite view of the different spheres of knowledge they are
to be studied; if not, not. The better part of ancient logic
appears hardly in our own day to have a separate existence; it is
absorbed in two other sciences: (1) rhetoric, if indeed this
ancient art be not also fading away into literary criticism; (2)
the science of language, under which all questions relating to
words and propositions and the combinations of them may properly be
included.To continue dead or imaginary sciences, which make no signs
of progress and have no definite sphere, tends to interfere with
the prosecution of living ones. The study of them is apt to blind
the judgment and to render men incapable of seeing the value of
evidence, and even of appreciating the nature of truth. Nor should
we allow the living science to become confused with the dead by an
ambiguity of language. The term logic has two different meanings,
an ancient and a modern one, and we vainly try to bridge the gulf
between them. Many perplexities are avoided by keeping them apart.
There might certainly be a new science of logic; it would not
however be built up out of the fragments of the old, but would be
distinct from them—relative to the state of knowledge which exists
at the present time, and based chiefly on the methods of Modern
Inductive philosophy. Such a science might have two legitimate
fields: first, the refutation and explanation of false philosophies
still hovering in the air as they appear from the point of view of
later experience or are comprehended in the history of the human
mind, as in a larger horizon: secondly, it might furnish new forms
of thought more adequate to the expression of all the diversities
and oppositions of knowledge which have grown up in these latter
days; it might also suggest new methods of enquiry derived from the
comparison of the sciences. Few will deny that the introduction of
the words 'subject' and 'object' and the Hegelian reconciliation of
opposites have been 'most gracious aids' to psychology, or that the
methods of Bacon and Mill have shed a light far and wide on the
realms of knowledge. These two great studies, the one destructive
and corrective of error, the other conservative and constructive of
truth, might be a first and second part of logic. Ancient logic
would be the propaedeutic or gate of approach to logical
science,—nothing more. But to pursue such speculations further,
though not irrelevant, might lead us too far away from the argument
of the dialogue.The Euthydemus is, of all the Dialogues of Plato, that in
which he approaches most nearly to the comic poet. The mirth is
broader, the irony more sustained, the contrast between Socrates
and the two Sophists, although veiled, penetrates deeper than in
any other of his writings. Even Thrasymachus, in the Republic, is
at last pacified, and becomes a friendly and interested auditor of
the great discourse. But in the Euthydemus the mask is never
dropped; the accustomed irony of Socrates continues to the
end...Socrates narrates to Crito a remarkable scene in which he has
himself taken part, and in which the two brothers, Dionysodorus and
Euthydemus, are the chief performers. They are natives of Chios,
who had settled at Thurii, but were driven out, and in former days
had been known at Athens as professors of rhetoric and of the art
of fighting in armour. To this they have now added a new
accomplishment—the art of Eristic, or fighting with words, which
they are likewise willing to teach 'for a consideration.' But they
can also teach virtue in a very short time and in the very best
manner. Socrates, who is always on the look-out for teachers of
virtue, is interested in the youth Cleinias, the grandson of the
great Alcibiades, and is desirous that he should have the benefit
of their instructions. He is ready to fall down and worship them;
although the greatness of their professions does arouse in his mind
a temporary incredulity.A circle gathers round them, in the midst of which are
Socrates, the two brothers, the youth Cleinias, who is watched by
the eager eyes of his lover Ctesippus, and others. The performance
begins; and such a performance as might well seem to require an
invocation of Memory and the Muses. It is agreed that the brothers
shall question Cleinias. 'Cleinias,' says Euthydemus, 'who learn,
the wise or the unwise?' 'The wise,' is the reply; given with
blushing and hesitation. 'And yet when you learned you did not know
and were not wise.' Then Dionysodorus takes up the ball: 'Who are
they who learn dictation of the grammar-master; the wise or the
foolish boys?' 'The wise.' 'Then, after all, the wise learn.' 'And
do they learn,' said Euthydemus, 'what they know or what they do
not know?' 'The latter.' 'And dictation is a dictation of letters?'
'Yes.' 'And you know letters?' 'Yes.' 'Then you learn what you
know.' 'But,' retorts Dionysodorus, 'is not learning acquiring
knowledge?' 'Yes.' 'And you acquire that which you have not got
already?' 'Yes.' 'Then you learn that which you do not
know.'Socrates is afraid that the youth Cleinias may be discouraged
at these repeated overthrows. He therefore explains to him the
nature of the process to which he is being subjected. The two
strangers are not serious; there are jests at the mysteries which
precede the enthronement, and he is being initiated into the
mysteries of the sophistical ritual. This is all a sort of
horse-play, which is now ended. The exhortation to virtue will
follow, and Socrates himself (if the wise men will not laugh at
him) is desirous of showing the way in which such an exhortation
should be carried on, according to his own poor notion. He proceeds
to question Cleinias. The result of the investigation may be summed
up as follows:—All men desire good; and good means the possession of goods,
such as wealth, health, beauty, birth, power, honour; not
forgetting the virtues and wisdom. And yet in this enumeration the
greatest good of all is omitted. What is that? Good fortune. But
what need is there of good fortune when we have wisdom already:—in
every art and business are not the wise also the fortunate? This is
admitted. And again, the possession of goods is not enough; there
must also be a right use of them which can only be given by
knowledge: in themselves they are neither good nor evil—knowledge
and wisdom are the only good, and ignorance and folly the only
evil. The conclusion is that we must get 'wisdom.' But can wisdom
be taught? 'Yes,' says Cleinias. The ingenuousness of the youth
delights Socrates, who is at once relieved from the necessity of
discussing one of his great puzzles. 'Since wisdom is the only
good, he must become a philosopher, or lover of wisdom.' 'That I
will,' says Cleinias.After Socrates has given this specimen of his own mode of
instruction, the two brothers recommence their exhortation to
virtue, which is of quite another sort.'You want Cleinias to be wise?' 'Yes.' 'And he is not wise
yet?' 'No.' 'Then you want him to be what he is not, and not to be
what he is?—not to be—that is, to perish. Pretty lovers and friends
you must all be!'Here Ctesippus, the lover of Cleinias, interposes in great
excitement, thinking that he will teach the two Sophists a lesson
of good manners. But he is quickly entangled in the meshes of their
sophistry; and as a storm seems to be gathering Socrates pacifies
him with a joke, and Ctesippus then says that he is not reviling
the two Sophists, he is only contradicting them. 'But,' says
Dionysodorus, 'there is no such thing as contradiction. When you
and I describe the same thing, or you describe one thing and I
describe another, how can there be a contradiction?' Ctesippus is
unable to reply.Socrates has already heard of the denial of contradiction,
and would like to be informed by the great master of the art, 'What
is the meaning of this paradox? Is there no such thing as error,
ignorance, falsehood? Then what are they professing to teach?' The
two Sophists complain that Socrates is ready to answer what they
said a year ago, but is 'non-plussed' at what they are saying now.
'What does the word "non-plussed" mean?' Socrates is informed, in
reply, that words are lifeless things, and lifeless things have no
sense or meaning. Ctesippus again breaks out, and again has to be
pacified by Socrates, who renews the conversation with Cleinias.
The two Sophists are like Proteus in the variety of their
transformations, and he, like Menelaus in the Odyssey, hopes to
restore them to their natural form.He had arrived at the conclusion that Cleinias must become a
philosopher. And philosophy is the possession of knowledge; and
knowledge must be of a kind which is profitable and may be used.
What knowledge is there which has such a nature? Not the knowledge
which is required in any particular art; nor again the art of the
composer of speeches, who knows how to write them, but cannot speak
them, although he too must be admitted to be a kind of enchanter of
wild animals. Neither is the knowledge which we are seeking the
knowledge of the general. For the general makes over his prey to
the statesman, as the huntsman does to the cook, or the taker of
quails to the keeper of quails; he has not the use of that which he
acquires. The two enquirers, Cleinias and Socrates, are described
as wandering about in a wilderness, vainly searching after the art
of life and happiness. At last they fix upon the kingly art, as
having the desired sort of knowledge. But the kingly art only gives
men those goods which are neither good nor evil: and if we say
further that it makes us wise, in what does it make us wise? Not in
special arts, such as cobbling or carpentering, but only in itself:
or say again that it makes us good, there is no answer to the
question, 'good in what?' At length in despair Cleinias and
Socrates turn to the 'Dioscuri' and request their aid.Euthydemus argues that Socrates knows something; and as he
cannot know and not know, he cannot know some things and not know
others, and therefore he knows all things: he and Dionysodorus and
all other men know all things. 'Do they know shoemaking, etc?'
'Yes.' The sceptical Ctesippus would like to have some evidence of
this extraordinary statement: he will believe if Euthydemus will
tell him how many teeth Dionysodorus has, and if Dionysodorus will
give him a like piece of information about Euthydemus. Even
Socrates is incredulous, and indulges in a little raillery at the
expense of the brothers. But he restrains himself, remembering that
if the men who are to be his teachers think him stupid they will
take no pains with him. Another fallacy is produced which turns on
the absoluteness of the verb 'to know.' And here Dionysodorus is
caught 'napping,' and is induced by Socrates to confess that 'he
does not know the good to be unjust.' Socrates appeals to his
brother Euthydemus; at the same time he acknowledges that he
cannot, like Heracles, fight against a Hydra, and even Heracles, on
the approach of a second monster, called upon his nephew Iolaus to
help. Dionysodorus rejoins that Iolaus was no more the nephew of
Heracles than of Socrates. For a nephew is a nephew, and a brother
is a brother, and a father is a father, not of one man only, but of
all; nor of men only, but of dogs and sea-monsters. Ctesippus makes
merry with the consequences which follow: 'Much good has your
father got out of the wisdom of his puppies.''But,' says Euthydemus, unabashed, 'nobody wants much good.'
Medicine is a good, arms are a good, money is a good, and yet there
may be too much of them in wrong places. 'No,' says Ctesippus,
'there cannot be too much gold.' And would you be happy if you had
three talents of gold in your belly, a talent in your pate, and a
stater in either eye?' Ctesippus, imitating the new wisdom,
replies, 'And do not the Scythians reckon those to be the happiest
of men who have their skulls gilded and see the inside of them?'
'Do you see,' retorts Euthydemus, 'what has the quality of vision
or what has not the quality of vision?' 'What has the quality of
vision.' 'And you see our garments?' 'Yes.' 'Then our garments have
the quality of vision.' A similar play of words follows, which is
successfully retorted by Ctesippus, to the great delight of
Cleinias, who is rebuked by Socrates for laughing at such solemn
and beautiful things.'But are there any beautiful things? And if there are such,
are they the same or not the same as absolute beauty?' Socrates
replies that they are not the same, but each of them has some
beauty present with it. 'And are you an ox because you have an ox
present with you?' After a few more amphiboliae, in which Socrates,
like Ctesippus, in self-defence borrows the weapons of the
brothers, they both confess that the two heroes are invincible; and
the scene concludes with a grand chorus of shouting and laughing,
and a panegyrical oration from Socrates:—First, he praises the indifference of Dionysodorus and
Euthydemus to public opinion; for most persons would rather be
refuted by such arguments than use them in the refutation of
others. Secondly, he remarks upon their impartiality; for they stop
their own mouths, as well as those of other people. Thirdly, he
notes their liberality, which makes them give away their secret to
all the world: they should be more reserved, and let no one be
present at this exhibition who does not pay them a handsome fee; or
better still they might practise on one another only. He concludes
with a respectful request that they will receive him and Cleinias
among their disciples.Crito tells Socrates that he has heard one of the audience
criticise severely this wisdom,—not sparing Socrates himself for
countenancing such an exhibition. Socrates asks what manner of man
was this censorious critic. 'Not an orator, but a great composer of
speeches.' Socrates understands that he is an amphibious animal,
half philosopher, half politician; one of a class who have the
highest opinion of themselves and a spite against philosophers,
whom they imagine to be their rivals. They are a class who are very
likely to get mauled by Euthydemus and his friends, and have a
great notion of their own wisdom; for they imagine themselves to
have all the advantages and none of the drawbacks both of politics
and of philosophy. They do not understand the principles of
combination, and hence are ignorant that the union of two good
things which have different ends produces a compound inferior to
either of them taken separately.Crito is anxious about the education of his children, one of
whom is growing up. The description of Dionysodorus and Euthydemus
suggests to him the reflection that the professors of education are
strange beings. Socrates consoles him with the remark that the good
in all professions are few, and recommends that 'he and his house'
should continue to serve philosophy, and not mind about its
professors....There is a stage in the history of philosophy in which the
old is dying out, and the new has not yet come into full life.
Great philosophies like the Eleatic or Heraclitean, which have
enlarged the boundaries of the human mind, begin to pass away in
words. They subsist only as forms which have rooted themselves in
language—as troublesome elements of thought which cannot be either
used or explained away. The same absoluteness which was once
attributed to abstractions is now attached to the words which are
the signs of them. The philosophy which in the first and second
generation was a great and inspiring effort of reflection, in the
third becomes sophistical, verbal, eristic.It is this stage of philosophy which Plato satirises in the
Euthydemus. The fallacies which are noted by him appear trifling to
us now, but they were not trifling in the age before logic, in the
decline of the earlier Greek philosophies, at a time when language
was first beginning to perplex human thought. Besides he is
caricaturing them; they probably received more subtle forms at the
hands of those who seriously maintained them. They are patent to us
in Plato, and we are inclined to wonder how any one could ever have
been deceived by them; but we must remember also that there was a
time when the human mind was only with great difficulty
disentangled from such fallacies.