Theaetetus
Theaetetus INTRODUCTION AND ANALYSIS.THEAETETUSCopyright
Theaetetus
Plato
INTRODUCTION AND ANALYSIS.
Some dialogues of Plato are of so various a character that
their relation to the other dialogues cannot be determined with any
degree of certainty. The Theaetetus, like the Parmenides, has
points of similarity both with his earlier and his later writings.
The perfection of style, the humour, the dramatic interest, the
complexity of structure, the fertility of illustration, the
shifting of the points of view, are characteristic of his best
period of authorship. The vain search, the negative conclusion, the
figure of the midwives, the constant profession of ignorance on the
part of Socrates, also bear the stamp of the early dialogues, in
which the original Socrates is not yet Platonized. Had we no other
indications, we should be disposed to range the Theaetetus with the
Apology and the Phaedrus, and perhaps even with the Protagoras and
the Laches.But when we pass from the style to an examination of the
subject, we trace a connection with the later rather than with the
earlier dialogues. In the first place there is the connexion,
indicated by Plato himself at the end of the dialogue, with the
Sophist, to which in many respects the Theaetetus is so little
akin. (1) The same persons reappear, including the younger
Socrates, whose name is just mentioned in the Theaetetus; (2) the
theory of rest, which Socrates has declined to consider, is resumed
by the Eleatic Stranger; (3) there is a similar allusion in both
dialogues to the meeting of Parmenides and Socrates (Theaet.,
Soph.); and (4) the inquiry into not-being in the Sophist
supplements the question of false opinion which is raised in the
Theaetetus. (Compare also Theaet. and Soph. for parallel turns of
thought.) Secondly, the later date of the dialogue is confirmed by
the absence of the doctrine of recollection and of any doctrine of
ideas except that which derives them from generalization and from
reflection of the mind upon itself. The general character of the
Theaetetus is dialectical, and there are traces of the same
Megarian influences which appear in the Parmenides, and which later
writers, in their matter of fact way, have explained by the
residence of Plato at Megara. Socrates disclaims the character of a
professional eristic, and also, with a sort of ironical admiration,
expresses his inability to attain the Megarian precision in the use
of terms. Yet he too employs a similar sophistical skill in
overturning every conceivable theory of knowledge.The direct indications of a date amount to no more than this:
the conversation is said to have taken place when Theaetetus was a
youth, and shortly before the death of Socrates. At the time of his
own death he is supposed to be a full-grown man. Allowing nine or
ten years for the interval between youth and manhood, the dialogue
could not have been written earlier than 390, when Plato was about
thirty-nine years of age. No more definite date is indicated by the
engagement in which Theaetetus is said to have fallen or to have
been wounded, and which may have taken place any time during the
Corinthian war, between the years 390-387. The later date which has
been suggested, 369, when the Athenians and Lacedaemonians disputed
the Isthmus with Epaminondas, would make the age of Theaetetus at
his death forty-five or forty-six. This a little impairs the beauty
of Socrates' remark, that 'he would be a great man if he
lived.'In this uncertainty about the place of the Theaetetus, it
seemed better, as in the case of the Republic, Timaeus, Critias, to
retain the order in which Plato himself has arranged this and the
two companion dialogues. We cannot exclude the possibility which
has been already noticed in reference to other works of Plato, that
the Theaetetus may not have been all written continuously; or the
probability that the Sophist and Politicus, which differ greatly in
style, were only appended after a long interval of time. The
allusion to Parmenides compared with the Sophist, would probably
imply that the dialogue which is called by his name was already in
existence; unless, indeed, we suppose the passage in which the
allusion occurs to have been inserted afterwards. Again, the
Theaetetus may be connected with the Gorgias, either dialogue from
different points of view containing an analysis of the real and
apparent (Schleiermacher); and both may be brought into relation
with the Apology as illustrating the personal life of Socrates. The
Philebus, too, may with equal reason be placed either after or
before what, in the language of Thrasyllus, may be called the
Second Platonic Trilogy. Both the Parmenides and the Sophist, and
still more the Theaetetus, have points of affinity with the
Cratylus, in which the principles of rest and motion are again
contrasted, and the Sophistical or Protagorean theory of language
is opposed to that which is attributed to the disciple of
Heracleitus, not to speak of lesser resemblances in thought and
language. The Parmenides, again, has been thought by some to hold
an intermediate position between the Theaetetus and the Sophist;
upon this view, the Sophist may be regarded as the answer to the
problems about One and Being which have been raised in the
Parmenides. Any of these arrangements may suggest new views to the
student of Plato; none of them can lay claim to an exclusive
probability in its favour.The Theaetetus is one of the narrated dialogues of Plato, and
is the only one which is supposed to have been written down. In a
short introductory scene, Euclides and Terpsion are described as
meeting before the door of Euclides' house in Megara. This may have
been a spot familiar to Plato (for Megara was within a walk of
Athens), but no importance can be attached to the accidental
introduction of the founder of the Megarian philosophy. The real
intention of the preface is to create an interest about the person
of Theaetetus, who has just been carried up from the army at
Corinth in a dying state. The expectation of his death recalls the
promise of his youth, and especially the famous conversation which
Socrates had with him when he was quite young, a few days before
his own trial and death, as we are once more reminded at the end of
the dialogue. Yet we may observe that Plato has himself forgotten
this, when he represents Euclides as from time to time coming to
Athens and correcting the copy from Socrates' own mouth. The
narrative, having introduced Theaetetus, and having guaranteed the
authenticity of the dialogue (compare Symposium, Phaedo,
Parmenides), is then dropped. No further use is made of the device.
As Plato himself remarks, who in this as in some other minute
points is imitated by Cicero (De Amicitia), the interlocutory words
are omitted.Theaetetus, the hero of the battle of Corinth and of the
dialogue, is a disciple of Theodorus, the great geometrician, whose
science is thus indicated to be the propaedeutic to philosophy. An
interest has been already excited about him by his approaching
death, and now he is introduced to us anew by the praises of his
master Theodorus. He is a youthful Socrates, and exhibits the same
contrast of the fair soul and the ungainly face and frame, the
Silenus mask and the god within, which are described in the
Symposium. The picture which Theodorus gives of his courage and
patience and intelligence and modesty is verified in the course of
the dialogue. His courage is shown by his behaviour in the battle,
and his other qualities shine forth as the argument proceeds.
Socrates takes an evident delight in 'the wise Theaetetus,' who has
more in him than 'many bearded men'; he is quite inspired by his
answers. At first the youth is lost in wonder, and is almost too
modest to speak, but, encouraged by Socrates, he rises to the
occasion, and grows full of interest and enthusiasm about the great
question. Like a youth, he has not finally made up his mind, and is
very ready to follow the lead of Socrates, and to enter into each
successive phase of the discussion which turns up. His great
dialectical talent is shown in his power of drawing distinctions,
and of foreseeing the consequences of his own answers. The enquiry
about the nature of knowledge is not new to him; long ago he has
felt the 'pang of philosophy,' and has experienced the youthful
intoxication which is depicted in the Philebus. But he has hitherto
been unable to make the transition from mathematics to metaphysics.
He can form a general conception of square and oblong numbers, but
he is unable to attain a similar expression of knowledge in the
abstract. Yet at length he begins to recognize that there are
universal conceptions of being, likeness, sameness, number, which
the mind contemplates in herself, and with the help of Socrates is
conducted from a theory of sense to a theory of ideas.There is no reason to doubt that Theaetetus was a real
person, whose name survived in the next generation. But neither can
any importance be attached to the notices of him in Suidas and
Proclus, which are probably based on the mention of him in Plato.
According to a confused statement in Suidas, who mentions him twice
over, first, as a pupil of Socrates, and then of Plato, he is said
to have written the first work on the Five Solids. But no early
authority cites the work, the invention of which may have been
easily suggested by the division of roots, which Plato attributes
to him, and the allusion to the backward state of solid geometry in
the Republic. At any rate, there is no occasion to recall him to
life again after the battle of Corinth, in order that we may allow
time for the completion of such a work (Muller). We may also remark
that such a supposition entirely destroys the pathetic interest of
the introduction.Theodorus, the geometrician, had once been the friend and
disciple of Protagoras, but he is very reluctant to leave his
retirement and defend his old master. He is too old to learn
Socrates' game of question and answer, and prefers the digressions
to the main argument, because he finds them easier to follow. The
mathematician, as Socrates says in the Republic, is not capable of
giving a reason in the same manner as the dialectician, and
Theodorus could not therefore have been appropriately introduced as
the chief respondent. But he may be fairly appealed to, when the
honour of his master is at stake. He is the 'guardian of his
orphans,' although this is a responsibility which he wishes to
throw upon Callias, the friend and patron of all Sophists,
declaring that he himself had early 'run away' from philosophy, and
was absorbed in mathematics. His extreme dislike to the Heraclitean
fanatics, which may be compared with the dislike of Theaetetus to
the materialists, and his ready acceptance of the noble words of
Socrates, are noticeable traits of character.The Socrates of the Theaetetus is the same as the Socrates of
the earlier dialogues. He is the invincible disputant, now advanced
in years, of the Protagoras and Symposium; he is still pursuing his
divine mission, his 'Herculean labours,' of which he has described
the origin in the Apology; and he still hears the voice of his
oracle, bidding him receive or not receive the truant souls. There
he is supposed to have a mission to convict men of self-conceit; in
the Theaetetus he has assigned to him by God the functions of a
man-midwife, who delivers men of their thoughts, and under this
character he is present throughout the dialogue. He is the true
prophet who has an insight into the natures of men, and can divine
their future; and he knows that sympathy is the secret power which
unlocks their thoughts. The hit at Aristides, the son of
Lysimachus, who was specially committed to his charge in the
Laches, may be remarked by the way. The attempt to discover the
definition of knowledge is in accordance with the character of
Socrates as he is described in the Memorabilia, asking What is
justice? what is temperance? and the like. But there is no reason
to suppose that he would have analyzed the nature of perception, or
traced the connexion of Protagoras and Heracleitus, or have raised
the difficulty respecting false opinion. The humorous
illustrations, as well as the serious thoughts, run through the
dialogue. The snubnosedness of Theaetetus, a characteristic which
he shares with Socrates, and the man-midwifery of Socrates, are not
forgotten in the closing words. At the end of the dialogue, as in
the Euthyphro, he is expecting to meet Meletus at the porch of the
king Archon; but with the same indifference to the result which is
everywhere displayed by him, he proposes that they shall reassemble
on the following day at the same spot. The day comes, and in the
Sophist the three friends again meet, but no further allusion is
made to the trial, and the principal share in the argument is
assigned, not to Socrates, but to an Eleatic stranger; the youthful
Theaetetus also plays a different and less independent part. And
there is no allusion in the Introduction to the second and third
dialogues, which are afterwards appended. There seems, therefore,
reason to think that there is a real change, both in the characters
and in the design.The dialogue is an enquiry into the nature of knowledge,
which is interrupted by two digressions. The first is the
digression about the midwives, which is also a leading thought or
continuous image, like the wave in the Republic, appearing and
reappearing at intervals. Again and again we are reminded that the
successive conceptions of knowledge are extracted from Theaetetus,
who in his turn truly declares that Socrates has got a great deal
more out of him than ever was in him. Socrates is never weary of
working out the image in humorous details,—discerning the symptoms
of labour, carrying the child round the hearth, fearing that
Theaetetus will bite him, comparing his conceptions to wind-eggs,
asserting an hereditary right to the occupation. There is also a
serious side to the image, which is an apt similitude of the
Socratic theory of education (compare Republic, Sophist), and
accords with the ironical spirit in which the wisest of men
delights to speak of himself.The other digression is the famous contrast of the lawyer and
philosopher. This is a sort of landing-place or break in the middle
of the dialogue. At the commencement of a great discussion, the
reflection naturally arises, How happy are they who, like the
philosopher, have time for such discussions (compare Republic)!
There is no reason for the introduction of such a digression; nor
is a reason always needed, any more than for the introduction of an
episode in a poem, or of a topic in conversation. That which is
given by Socrates is quite sufficient, viz. that the philosopher
may talk and write as he pleases. But though not very closely
connected, neither is the digression out of keeping with the rest
of the dialogue. The philosopher naturally desires to pour forth
the thoughts which are always present to him, and to discourse of
the higher life. The idea of knowledge, although hard to be
defined, is realised in the life of philosophy. And the contrast is
the favourite antithesis between the world, in the various
characters of sophist, lawyer, statesman, speaker, and the
philosopher,—between opinion and knowledge,—between the
conventional and the true.The greater part of the dialogue is devoted to setting up and
throwing down definitions of science and knowledge. Proceeding from
the lower to the higher by three stages, in which perception,
opinion, reasoning are successively examined, we first get rid of
the confusion of the idea of knowledge and specific kinds of
knowledge,—a confusion which has been already noticed in the Lysis,
Laches, Meno, and other dialogues. In the infancy of logic, a form
of thought has to be invented before the content can be filled up.
We cannot define knowledge until the nature of definition has been
ascertained. Having succeeded in making his meaning plain, Socrates
proceeds to analyze (1) the first definition which Theaetetus
proposes: 'Knowledge is sensible perception.' This is speedily
identified with the Protagorean saying, 'Man is the measure of all
things;' and of this again the foundation is discovered in the
perpetual flux of Heracleitus. The relativeness of sensation is
then developed at length, and for a moment the definition appears
to be accepted. But soon the Protagorean thesis is pronounced to be
suicidal; for the adversaries of Protagoras are as good a measure
as he is, and they deny his doctrine. He is then supposed to reply
that the perception may be true at any given instant. But the reply
is in the end shown to be inconsistent with the Heraclitean
foundation, on which the doctrine has been affirmed to rest. For if
the Heraclitean flux is extended to every sort of change in every
instant of time, how can any thought or word be detained even for
an instant? Sensible perception, like everything else, is tumbling
to pieces. Nor can Protagoras himself maintain that one man is as
good as another in his knowledge of the future; and 'the
expedient,' if not 'the just and true,' belongs to the sphere of
the future.And so we must ask again, What is knowledge? The comparison
of sensations with one another implies a principle which is above
sensation, and which resides in the mind itself. We are thus led to
look for knowledge in a higher sphere, and accordingly Theaetetus,
when again interrogated, replies (2) that 'knowledge is true
opinion.' But how is false opinion possible? The Megarian or
Eristic spirit within us revives the question, which has been
already asked and indirectly answered in the Meno: 'How can a man
be ignorant of that which he knows?' No answer is given to this not
unanswerable question. The comparison of the mind to a block of
wax, or to a decoy of birds, is found wanting.But are we not inverting the natural order in looking for
opinion before we have found knowledge? And knowledge is not true
opinion; for the Athenian dicasts have true opinion but not
knowledge. What then is knowledge? We answer (3), 'True opinion,
with definition or explanation.' But all the different ways in
which this statement may be understood are set aside, like the
definitions of courage in the Laches, or of friendship in the
Lysis, or of temperance in the Charmides. At length we arrive at
the conclusion, in which nothing is concluded.There are two special difficulties which beset the student of
the Theaetetus: (1) he is uncertain how far he can trust Plato's
account of the theory of Protagoras; and he is also uncertain (2)
how far, and in what parts of the dialogue, Plato is expressing his
own opinion. The dramatic character of the work renders the answer
to both these questions difficult.1. In reply to the first, we have only probabilities to
offer. Three main points have to be decided: (a) Would Protagoras
have identified his own thesis, 'Man is the measure of all things,'
with the other, 'All knowledge is sensible perception'? (b) Would
he have based the relativity of knowledge on the Heraclitean flux?
(c) Would he have asserted the absoluteness of sensation at each
instant? Of the work of Protagoras on 'Truth' we know nothing, with
the exception of the two famous fragments, which are cited in this
dialogue, 'Man is the measure of all things,' and, 'Whether there
are gods or not, I cannot tell.' Nor have we any other trustworthy
evidence of the tenets of Protagoras, or of the sense in which his
words are used. For later writers, including Aristotle in his
Metaphysics, have mixed up the Protagoras of Plato, as they have
the Socrates of Plato, with the real person.Returning then to the Theaetetus, as the only possible source
from which an answer to these questions can be obtained, we may
remark, that Plato had 'The Truth' of Protagoras before him, and
frequently refers to the book. He seems to say expressly, that in
this work the doctrine of the Heraclitean flux was not to be found;
'he told the real truth' (not in the book, which is so entitled,
but) 'privately to his disciples,'—words which imply that the
connexion between the doctrines of Protagoras and Heracleitus was
not generally recognized in Greece, but was really discovered or
invented by Plato. On the other hand, the doctrine that 'Man is the
measure of all things,' is expressly identified by Socrates with
the other statement, that 'What appears to each man is to him;' and
a reference is made to the books in which the statement
occurs;—this Theaetetus, who has 'often read the books,' is
supposed to acknowledge (so Cratylus). And Protagoras, in the
speech attributed to him, never says that he has been
misunderstood: he rather seems to imply that the absoluteness of
sensation at each instant was to be found in his words. He is only
indignant at the 'reductio ad absurdum' devised by Socrates for his
'homo mensura,' which Theodorus also considers to be 'really too
bad.'The question may be raised, how far Plato in the Theaetetus
could have misrepresented Protagoras without violating the laws of
dramatic probability. Could he have pretended to cite from a
well-known writing what was not to be found there? But such a
shadowy enquiry is not worth pursuing further. We need only
remember that in the criticism which follows of the thesis of
Protagoras, we are criticizing the Protagoras of Plato, and not
attempting to draw a precise line between his real sentiments and
those which Plato has attributed to him.2. The other difficulty is a more subtle, and also a more
important one, because bearing on the general character of the
Platonic dialogues. On a first reading of them, we are apt to
imagine that the truth is only spoken by Socrates, who is never
guilty of a fallacy himself, and is the great detector of the
errors and fallacies of others. But this natural presumption is
disturbed by the discovery that the Sophists are sometimes in the
right and Socrates in the wrong. Like the hero of a novel, he is
not to be supposed always to represent the sentiments of the
author. There are few modern readers who do not side with
Protagoras, rather than with Socrates, in the dialogue which is
called by his name. The Cratylus presents a similar difficulty: in
his etymologies, as in the number of the State, we cannot tell how
far Socrates is serious; for the Socratic irony will not allow him
to distinguish between his real and his assumed wisdom. No one is
the superior of the invincible Socrates in argument (except in the
first part of the Parmenides, where he is introduced as a youth);
but he is by no means supposed to be in possession of the whole
truth. Arguments are often put into his mouth (compare Introduction
to the Gorgias) which must have seemed quite as untenable to Plato
as to a modern writer. In this dialogue a great part of the answer
of Protagoras is just and sound; remarks are made by him on verbal
criticism, and on the importance of understanding an opponent's
meaning, which are conceived in the true spirit of philosophy. And
the distinction which he is supposed to draw between Eristic and
Dialectic, is really a criticism of Plato on himself and his own
criticism of Protagoras.The difficulty seems to arise from not attending to the
dramatic character of the writings of Plato. There are two, or
more, sides to questions; and these are parted among the different
speakers. Sometimes one view or aspect of a question is made to
predominate over the rest, as in the Gorgias or Sophist; but in
other dialogues truth is divided, as in the Laches and Protagoras,
and the interest of the piece consists in the contrast of opinions.
The confusion caused by the irony of Socrates, who, if he is true
to his character, cannot say anything of his own knowledge, is
increased by the circumstance that in the Theaetetus and some other
dialogues he is occasionally playing both parts himself, and even
charging his own arguments with unfairness. In the Theaetetus he is
designedly held back from arriving at a conclusion. For we cannot
suppose that Plato conceived a definition of knowledge to be
impossible. But this is his manner of approaching and surrounding a
question. The lights which he throws on his subject are indirect,
but they are not the less real for that. He has no intention of
proving a thesis by a cut-and-dried argument; nor does he imagine
that a great philosophical problem can be tied up within the limits
of a definition. If he has analyzed a proposition or notion, even
with the severity of an impossible logic, if half-truths have been
compared by him with other half-truths, if he has cleared up or
advanced popular ideas, or illustrated a new method, his aim has
been sufficiently accomplished.The writings of Plato belong to an age in which the power of
analysis had outrun the means of knowledge; and through a spurious
use of dialectic, the distinctions which had been already 'won from
the void and formless infinite,' seemed to be rapidly returning to
their original chaos. The two great speculative philosophies, which
a century earlier had so deeply impressed the mind of Hellas, were
now degenerating into Eristic. The contemporaries of Plato and
Socrates were vainly trying to find new combinations of them, or to
transfer them from the object to the subject. The Megarians, in
their first attempts to attain a severer logic, were making
knowledge impossible (compare Theaet.). They were asserting 'the
one good under many names,' and, like the Cynics, seem to have
denied predication, while the Cynics themselves were depriving
virtue of all which made virtue desirable in the eyes of Socrates
and Plato. And besides these, we find mention in the later writings
of Plato, especially in the Theaetetus, Sophist, and Laws, of
certain impenetrable godless persons, who will not believe what
they 'cannot hold in their hands'; and cannot be approached in
argument, because they cannot argue (Theat; Soph.). No school of
Greek philosophers exactly answers to these persons, in whom Plato
may perhaps have blended some features of the Atomists with the
vulgar materialistic tendencies of mankind in general (compare
Introduction to the Sophist).And not only was there a conflict of opinions, but the stage
which the mind had reached presented other difficulties hardly
intelligible to us, who live in a different cycle of human thought.
All times of mental progress are times of confusion; we only see,
or rather seem to see things clearly, when they have been long
fixed and defined. In the age of Plato, the limits of the world of
imagination and of pure abstraction, of the old world and the new,
were not yet fixed. The Greeks, in the fourth century before
Christ, had no words for 'subject' and 'object,' and no distinct
conception of them; yet they were always hovering about the
question involved in them. The analysis of sense, and the analysis
of thought, were equally difficult to them; and hopelessly confused
by the attempt to solve them, not through an appeal to facts, but
by the help of general theories respecting the nature of the
universe.Plato, in his Theaetetus, gathers up the sceptical tendencies
of his age, and compares them. But he does not seek to reconstruct
out of them a theory of knowledge. The time at which such a theory
could be framed had not yet arrived. For there was no measure of
experience with which the ideas swarming in men's minds could be
compared; the meaning of the word 'science' could scarcely be
explained to them, except from the mathematical sciences, which
alone offered the type of universality and certainty. Philosophy
was becoming more and more vacant and abstract, and not only the
Platonic Ideas and the Eleatic Being, but all abstractions seemed
to be at variance with sense and at war with one
another.The want of the Greek mind in the fourth century before
Christ was not another theory of rest or motion, or Being or atoms,
but rather a philosophy which could free the mind from the power of
abstractions and alternatives, and show how far rest and how far
motion, how far the universal principle of Being and the
multitudinous principle of atoms, entered into the composition of
the world; which could distinguish between the true and false
analogy, and allow the negative as well as the positive a place in
human thought. To such a philosophy Plato, in the Theaetetus,
offers many contributions. He has followed philosophy into the
region of mythology, and pointed out the similarities of opposing
phases of thought. He has also shown that extreme abstractions are
self-destructive, and, indeed, hardly distinguishable from one
another. But his intention is not to unravel the whole subject of
knowledge, if this had been possible; and several times in the
course of the dialogue he rejects explanations of knowledge which
have germs of truth in them; as, for example, 'the resolution of
the compound into the simple;' or 'right opinion with a mark of
difference.'...Terpsion, who has come to Megara from the country, is
described as having looked in vain for Euclides in the Agora; the
latter explains that he has been down to the harbour, and on his
way thither had met Theaetetus, who was being carried up from the
army to Athens. He was scarcely alive, for he had been badly
wounded at the battle of Corinth, and had taken the dysentery which
prevailed in the camp. The mention of his condition suggests the
reflection, 'What a loss he will be!' 'Yes, indeed,' replies
Euclid; 'only just now I was hearing of his noble conduct in the
battle.' 'That I should expect; but why did he not remain at
Megara?' 'I wanted him to remain, but he would not; so I went with
him as far as Erineum; and as I parted from him, I remembered that
Socrates had seen him when he was a youth, and had a remarkable
conversation with him, not long before his own death; and he then
prophesied of him that he would be a great man if he lived.' 'How
true that has been; how like all that Socrates said! And could you
repeat the conversation?' 'Not from memory; but I took notes when I
returned home, which I afterwards filled up at leisure, and got
Socrates to correct them from time to time, when I came to
Athens'...Terpsion had long intended to ask for a sight of this
writing, of which he had already heard. They are both tired, and
agree to rest and have the conversation read to them by a
servant...'Here is the roll, Terpsion; I need only observe that I
have omitted, for the sake of convenience, the interlocutory words,
"said I," "said he"; and that Theaetetus, and Theodorus, the
geometrician of Cyrene, are the persons with whom Socrates is
conversing.'Socrates begins by asking Theodorus whether, in his visit to
Athens, he has found any Athenian youth likely to attain
distinction in science. 'Yes, Socrates, there is one very
remarkable youth, with whom I have become acquainted. He is no
beauty, and therefore you need not imagine that I am in love with
him; and, to say the truth, he is very like you, for he has a snub
nose, and projecting eyes, although these features are not so
marked in him as in you. He combines the most various qualities,
quickness, patience, courage; and he is gentle as well as wise,
always silently flowing on, like a river of oil. Look! he is the
middle one of those who are entering the palaestra.'Socrates, who does not know his name, recognizes him as the
son of Euphronius, who was himself a good man and a rich. He is
informed by Theodorus that the youth is named Theaetetus, but the
property of his father has disappeared in the hands of trustees;
this does not, however, prevent him from adding liberality to his
other virtues. At the desire of Socrates he invites Theaetetus to
sit by them.'Yes,' says Socrates, 'that I may see in you, Theaetetus, the
image of my ugly self, as Theodorus declares. Not that his remark
is of any importance; for though he is a philosopher, he is not a
painter, and therefore he is no judge of our faces; but, as he is a
man of science, he may be a judge of our intellects. And if he were
to praise the mental endowments of either of us, in that case the
hearer of the eulogy ought to examine into what he says, and the
subject should not refuse to be examined.' Theaetetus consents, and
is caught in a trap (compare the similar trap which is laid for
Theodorus). 'Then, Theaetetus, you will have to be examined, for
Theodorus has been praising you in a style of which I never heard
the like.' 'He was only jesting.' 'Nay, that is not his way; and I
cannot allow you, on that pretence, to retract the assent which you
have already given, or I shall make Theodorus repeat your praises,
and swear to them.' Theaetetus, in reply, professes that he is
willing to be examined, and Socrates begins by asking him what he
learns of Theodorus. He is himself anxious to learn anything of
anybody; and now he has a little question to which he wants
Theaetetus or Theodorus (or whichever of the company would not be
'donkey' to the rest) to find an answer. Without further preface,
but at the same time apologizing for his eagerness, he asks, 'What
is knowledge?' Theodorus is too old to answer questions, and begs
him to interrogate Theaetetus, who has the advantage of
youth.Theaetetus replies, that knowledge is what he learns of
Theodorus, i.e. geometry and arithmetic; and that there are other
kinds of knowledge—shoemaking, carpentering, and the like. But
Socrates rejoins, that this answer contains too much and also too
little. For although Theaetetus has enumerated several kinds of
knowledge, he has not explained the common nature of them; as if he
had been asked, 'What is clay?' and instead of saying 'Clay is
moistened earth,' he had answered, 'There is one clay of
image-makers, another of potters, another of oven-makers.'
Theaetetus at once divines that Socrates means him to extend to all
kinds of knowledge the same process of generalization which he has
already learned to apply to arithmetic. For he has discovered a
division of numbers into square numbers, 4, 9, 16, etc., which are
composed of equal factors, and represent figures which have equal
sides, and oblong numbers, 3, 5, 6, 7, etc., which are composed of
unequal factors, and represent figures which have unequal sides.
But he has never succeeded in attaining a similar conception of
knowledge, though he has often tried; and, when this and similar
questions were brought to him from Socrates, has been sorely
distressed by them. Socrates explains to him that he is in labour.
For men as well as women have pangs of labour; and both at times
require the assistance of midwives. And he, Socrates, is a midwife,
although this is a secret; he has inherited the art from his mother
bold and bluff, and he ushers into light, not children, but the
thoughts of men. Like the midwives, who are 'past bearing
children,' he too can have no offspring—the God will not allow him
to bring anything into the world of his own. He also reminds
Theaetetus that the midwives are or ought to be the only
matchmakers (this is the preparation for a biting jest); for those
who reap the fruit are most likely to know on what soil the plants
will grow. But respectable midwives avoid this department of
practice—they do not want to be called procuresses. There are some
other differences between the two sorts of pregnancy. For women do
not bring into the world at one time real children and at another
time idols which are with difficulty distinguished from them. 'At
first,' says Socrates in his character of the man-midwife, 'my
patients are barren and stolid, but after a while they "round
apace," if the gods are propitious to them; and this is due not to
me but to themselves; I and the god only assist in bringing their
ideas to the birth. Many of them have left me too soon, and the
result has been that they have produced abortions; or when I have
delivered them of children they have lost them by an ill bringing
up, and have ended by seeing themselves, as others see them, to be
great fools. Aristides, the son of Lysimachus, is one of these, and
there have been others. The truants often return to me and beg to
be taken back; and then, if my familiar allows me, which is not
always the case, I receive them, and they begin to grow again.
There come to me also those who have nothing in them, and have no
need of my art; and I am their matchmaker (see above), and marry
them to Prodicus or some other inspired sage who is likely to suit
them. I tell you this long story because I suspect that you are in
labour. Come then to me, who am a midwife, and the son of a
midwife, and I will deliver you. And do not bite me, as the women
do, if I abstract your first-born; for I am acting out of good-will
towards you; the God who is within me is the friend of man, though
he will not allow me to dissemble the truth. Once more then,
Theaetetus, I repeat my old question—"What is knowledge?" Take
courage, and by the help of God you will discover an answer.' 'My
answer is, that knowledge is perception.' 'That is the theory of
Protagoras, who has another way of expressing the same thing when
he says, "Man is the measure of all things." He was a very wise
man, and we should try to understand him. In order to illustrate
his meaning let me suppose that there is the same wind blowing in
our faces, and one of us may be hot and the other cold. How is
this? Protagoras will reply that the wind is hot to him who is
cold, cold to him who is hot. And "is" means "appears," and when
you say "appears to him," that means "he feels." Thus feeling,
appearance, perception, coincide with being. I suspect, however,
that this was only a "facon de parler," by which he imposed on the
common herd like you and me; he told "the truth" (in allusion to
the title of his book, which was called "The Truth") in secret to
his disciples. For he was really a votary of that famous philosophy
in which all things are said to be relative; nothing is great or
small, or heavy or light, or one, but all is in motion and mixture
and transition and flux and generation, not "being," as we
ignorantly affirm, but "becoming." This has been the doctrine, not
of Protagoras only, but of all philosophers, with the single
exception of Parmenides; Empedocles, Heracleitus, and others, and
all the poets, with Epicharmus, the king of Comedy, and Homer, the
king of Tragedy, at their head, have said the same; the latter has
these words—"Ocean, whence the gods sprang, and mother
Tethys."