33,99 €
This major new study by one of the most penetrating and persistent critics of philosophical and scientific orthodoxy, returns to Aristotle in order to examine the salient categories in terms of which we think about ourselves and our nature, and the distinctive forms of explanation we invoke to render ourselves intelligible to ourselves.
Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:
Seitenzahl: 696
Veröffentlichungsjahr: 2011
Contents
Preface
1 The Project
1. Human nature
2. Philosophical anthropology
3. Grammatical investigation
4. Philosophical investigation
5. Philosophy and ‘mere words’
6. A challenge to the autonomy of the philosophical enterprise: Quine
7. The Platonic and Aristotelian traditions in philosophical anthropology
2 Substance
1. Substances: things
2. Substances: stuffs
3. Substance-referring expressions
4. Conceptual connections between things and stuffs
5. Substances and their substantial parts
6. Substances conceived as natural kinds
7. Substances conceived as a common logico-linguistic category
8. A historical digression: misconceptions of the category of substance
3 Causation
1. Causation: Humean, neo-Humean and anti-Humean
2. On causal necessity
3. Event causation is not a prototype
4. The inadequacy of Hume’s analysis: observability, spatio-temporal relations and regularity
5. The flaw in the early modern debate
6. Agent causation as prototype
7. Agent causation is only a prototype
8. Event causation and other centres of variation
9. Overview
4 Powers
1. Possibility
2. Powers of the inanimate
3. Active and passive powers of the inanimate
4. Power and its actualization
5. Power and its vehicle
6. First- and second-order powers; loss of power
7. Human powers: basic distinctions
8. Human powers: further distinctions
9. Dispositions
5 Agency
1. Inanimate agents
2. Inanimate needs
3. Animate agents: needs and wants
4. Volitional agency: preliminaries
5. Doings, acts and actions
6. Human agency and action
7. A historical overview
8. Human action as agential causation of movement
6 Teleology and Teleological Explanation
1. Teleology and purpose
2. What things have a purpose?
3. Purpose and axiology
4. The beneficial
5. A historical digression: teleology and causality
7 Reasons and Explanation of Human Action
1. Rationality and reasonableness
2. Reason, reasoning and reasons
3. Explaining human behaviour
4. Explanation in terms of agential reasons
5. Causal mythologies
8 The Mind
1. Homo loquens
2. The Cartesian mind
3. The nature of the mind
9 The Self and the Body
1. The emergence of the philosophers’ self
2. The illusion of the philosophers’ self
3. The body
4. The relationship between human beings and their bodies
10 The Person
1. The emergence of the concept
2. An unholy trinity: Descartes, Locke and Hume
3. Changing bodies and switching brains: puzzle cases and red herrings
4. The concept of a person
Index
Recent books by P. M. S. Hacker published by Wiley-Blackwell
Wittgenstein’s Place in Twentieth-Century Analytic Philosophy (1996)
Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience (2003), co-authored with M. R. Bennett
Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning, Volume 1 of An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, Part I – Essays (2005), co-authored with G. P. Baker, second, extensively revised edition by P. M. S. Hacker
Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning, Volume 1 of An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, Part II – Exegesis 1–184 (2005), co-authored with G. P. Baker, second, extensively revised edition by P. M. S. Hacker
History of Cognitive Neuroscience (2008), co-authored with M. R. Bennett
Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar, and Necessity, Volume 2 of an Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations – Essays and Exegesis of 185–242 (2009), co-authored with G. P. Baker, second, extensively revised edition by P. M. S. Hacker
This paperback edition first published 2010
© 2010 by P. M. S. Hacker.
Edition history: Blackwell Publishing Ltd (hardback, 2007)
Blackwell Publishing was acquired by John Wiley & Sons in February 2007.
Blackwell’s publishing program has been merged with Wiley’s global Scientific, Technical, and Medical business to form Wiley-Blackwell.
Registered Office
John Wiley & Sons Ltd, The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, United Kingdom
Editorial Offices
350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148–5020, USA
9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK
The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK
For details of our global editorial offices, for customer services, and for information about how to apply for permission to reuse the copyright material in this book please see our website at www.wiley.com/wiley-blackwell.
The right of P. M. S. Hacker to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher.
Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books.
Designations used by companies to distinguish their products are often claimed as trademarks. All brand names and product names used in this book are trade names, service marks, trademarks or registered trademarks of their respective owners. The publisher is not associated with any product or vendor mentioned in this book. This publication is designed to provide accurate and authoritative information in regard to the subject matter covered. It is sold on the understanding that the publisher is not engaged in rendering professional services. If professional advice or other expert assistance is required, the services of a competent professional should be sought.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Hacker, P. M. S. (Peter Michael Stephan)
Human nature : the categorial framework / P. M. S. Hacker.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-1-4051-4728-6 (hardback: alk. paper) — 978-1-4443-3248-3
(paperback : alk. paper) 1. Philosophical anthropology. I. Title.
BD450.H2355 2007
128—dc22
2006103171
A catalogue record for this title is available from the British Library.
Set in 10.5/12.5pt Sabon
by Graphicraft Limited, Hong Kong
Printed and bound in Singapore
by Markono Print Media Pte Ltd
For
Hans Oberdiek
Preface
Philosophy is of little worth unless it aspires to give an overview of a whole domain of thought, to display the ramifying network of conceptual relationships that characterize it, and to resolve problems and puzzlements that characteristically accompany reflection on it. As I reached the end of my academic career, I felt a powerful urge to paint a last large fresco that would depict, sometimes with broad brush, sometimes in fine detail, themes which I had studied and reflected on for the last forty years. The domain I have striven to portray in this book is that of human nature. I have tried to give a perspicuous representation of the most fundamental concepts and conceptual forms in terms of which we think about ourselves. These range from the most general categorial concepts of substance, causation, power and agency to the more specific and specifically anthropological concepts of rationality, mind, body and person. This book, Human Nature: The Categorial Framework, sketches the structural background and paints the central landmarks of the panorama I have in view. I intend to continue my endeavours in a volume entitled HumanNature: The Cognitive and Cogitative Powers that will add to the fresco more and finer detail. If time and fortune permit, I hope to write a concluding volume, Human Nature: The Affective and Moral Powers.
To enable readers, especially students, to take in at a glance some parts of my argument and some of the classifications elaborated, I introduced the occasional tree diagram and comparative list. These are often no more than illustrations to the text, sometimes over- simplifying for purposes of surveyability. They are meant to illuminate the argument, as a picture illustrates a story, not to be a substitute for it.
Many friends and acquaintances have encouraged me and given me moral support in the course of writing this book. One of the delights of philosophy is discussion with others who toil on the same rocky pathways and jungle trails, and who not only hold out a helping hand when one slips, and correct one when one takes a wrong path, but also help one blaze a trail. I have been blessed with such friends. If, in the course of these numerous discussions, merriment kept breaking through – as indeed it did – I never found this an impediment to philosophy, but a mark of shared delight in the common pursuit of understanding.
I am grateful to Maria Alvarez, Erich Ammereller, Hanoch Ben-Yami, Stephan Blatti, John Dupré, Hanjo Glock, the late Oswald Hanfling, John Hyman, Wolfgang Künne, Anselm Müller, Bede Rundle, Con- stantine Sandis, the late Peter Strawson, and David Wiggins, who all read one or more (and some read many more) of the chapters and gave me the great benefit of their criticisms and suggestions. I should like to record my gratitude to Anthony Kenny, whose encouragement in this enterprise, as in others in the past, spurred me on. I have learnt more from his luminous writings and incisive remarks than I can say. I owe a special debt to Hans Oberdiek and to Herman Philipse, who kindly read the whole draft, and whose detailed comments and suggestions were invaluable. I am, as I have so often been in the past, much indebted to Jean van Altena for her expert copy-editing and judicious advice.
I am happy to record my gratitude to my college, St John’s, which is unstinting in its support of scholarship, the pursuit of knowledge and the quest for understanding.
Chapter 2 of this book is a modified version of the paper entitled ‘Substance: Things and Stuffs’, published in the Proceedings of theAristotelian Society, suppl. vol. 78 (2004), pp. 41–63. A much short- ened version of chapters 8 and 9 was delivered as a plenary lecture at Kirchberg, August 2006, and is to be published in the Proceedingsof the 29thInternational Wittgenstein Symposium. A variant of the same paper was delivered as the opening address at the meeting of the British Society for the Philosophy of Education in Oxford, March 2006. A part of chapter 7 is to be published in Constantine Sandis (ed.), New Essays on the Explanation of Action.
P. M. S. Hacker
St John’s College, Oxford
July 2006
. . . les principes sont dans l’usage commun et devant les yeux de tout le monde. On n’a que faire de tourner la tête, ni de se faire violence; il n’est question que d’avoir bonne vue. Mais il faut l’avoir bonne, car les principes sont si déliés, et en si grand nombre qu’il est presque impossible qu’il n’en échappe. Or l’omission d’un principe mène a l’erreur. Ainsi il faut avoir la vue bien nette pour voir tous les principes, et ensuite l’esprit juste pour ne pas raisonner faussement sur des principes connus.
. . . the principles are found in common use, and are there for all to see. One has only to look, and no effort is necessary; it is only a question of good eyesight, but it must be good, for the principles are so subtle and numerous, that it is almost impossible but that some escape notice. Now the omission of one principle leads to error; so one needs very clear sight to see all the principles, as well as an accurate mind to avoid drawing false conclusions from known principles.
Pascal, Pensées, I, 1
1
The Project
1. Human nature
Human beings are animals with a distinctive range of abilities. Though they have a mind, they are not identical with the mind they have. Though they have a body, they are not identical with the body they have. Nor is a human being a conjunction of a mind and a body that causally interact with each other. Like other animals, human beings have a brain on the normal functioning of which their powers depend. But a human person is not a brain enclosed in a skull. A mature human being is a self-conscious agent, with the ability to act, and to react in thought, feeling and deed, for reasons.
Animals, like inanimate objects, are spatio-temporal continuants. They have a physical location and trace a continuous spatio-temporal path through the world. In this sense, they are, like familiar material objects, bodies located on, and moving on, the face of the earth. They are substances, persistent individual things that are classifiable into various substantial kinds according to their nature and our interests. (What counts as such a classifying noun will be examined in chapter 2.) Animals are animate substances – living things. So, unlike mere material objects, they ingest matter from their environment and metabolize it in order to provide energy for their growth, their distinctive forms of activity, and their reproduction. Unlike plants, animals are sentient agents, and all but the lowliest forms of animal life are also self-moving. Their sentience is exhibited in their exercise of the sensefaculties they possess: for example, the perceptual faculties of sight, hearing, smell, taste and feeling, and in the actualization of their passive powers of sensation: for example, susceptibility to pain, kinaesthetic sensation and liability to overall bodily feelings, such as feeling tired, and feelings of overall condition, such as feeling well. The perceptual faculties are cognitive. They are sources of knowledge about the perceptible environment. It is by the exercise of these sense-faculties, by the use of the sense-organs that are their vehicles, that animals learn about the objects in, and features of, their environment. Being sentient and being self-moving are complementary powers of animal agency. For an animal that can learn how things are in its vicinity exhibits what it has apprehended both in its finding the things it seeks (such as food, protective environment, a mate) and in its avoiding obstacles and dangers. The criteria for whether an animal has perceived something lie in its responsive behaviour – so perception, knowledge and belief, affection, desire and action are conceptually linked.
The abilities distinctive of human beings are abilities of intellect and will. The relevant abilities of intellect are thought, imagination (the cogitative and creative imagination rather than the image-generating faculty), personal (experiential) and factual memory, reasoning and selfconsciousness. Human beings have the ability to think of (and imagine) things that lie beyond their present perceptual field – to think of things as encountered in the past and of the encountering of them, of past things learnt about and of the learning of them, of future things that do not yet exist and of eventualities and actions that have not yet occurred or been performed. To the extent that other higher animals possess comparable abilities, then they do so only in rudimentary (prelinguistic) forms. Humans can think both of what does and also of what does not exist or occur, of what has or has not been done, and of what will and what will not be done. We can believe, imagine, hope or fear that such-and-such is the case, irrespective of whether things are so or not. In short, thought, both in rudimentary form in animals and in developed form in humans, displays intentionality. Not only can we think of and about such things, and think that things are thus-and-so, but we can reason from such premisses to conclusions that follow from or are well supported by them. And we can evaluate such reasoning as valid or invalid, plausible or implausible. Because the horizon of human thinking is so much wider than that of non-human animal thinking, so too the horizon of human feelings and emotions is far wider than that of other animals. Both humans and animals can hope and fear things, but many of the things that humans can hope for (such as salvation, or good weather next week) and fear (such as damnation, or bad weather next week) are not possible objects of corresponding animal emotions.
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!