Solving, Resolving, and Dissolving Philosophical Problems - P. M. S. Hacker - E-Book

Solving, Resolving, and Dissolving Philosophical Problems E-Book

P. M. S. Hacker

0,0
27,99 €

-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

Equips readers with the intellectual tools required to tackle perennial philosophical problems

Solving, Resolving, and Dissolving Philosophical Problems is addressed to all who are interested in philosophical questions. It presupposes little philosophical knowledge, only curiosity and an open mind. It demands a willingness to learn not doctrine but method, and the courage to suspend judgement and to challenge received ideas.

Advocating the method of the 3 C-s: Connective, Contrastive, and Contextual Analysis, the book demonstrates the method by putting it to work — examining fifteen salient philosophical questions that concern all thinking people. It is organized thematically into four parts. Part I introduces questions in philosophy of psychology (the nature of the mind; the mind/body problem; the nature of consciousness and its demystification; knowledge of other minds). Part II deals with epistemological questions (knowledge, belief; memory; imagination, thinking; dreaming). Part III deals with value (the roots of morality; the nature of good and evil; the need for a secular conception of the soul; happiness). The application of the method in the essays produces striking, original and unanticipated results that will give readers pause. The final part of the book articulates in detail the methodology of the 3 C-s exemplified by the fifteen essays and defends it against objections.

Solving, Resolving, and Dissolving Philosophical Problems: On the Methodology of Connective, Contrastive, and Contextual Analysis is an excellent textbook for undergraduate students in introductory philosophy courses alongside more advanced scholars, as well as an invaluable resource for educated general readers with an interest in philosophical methodology.

Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:

Android
iOS
von Legimi
zertifizierten E-Readern

Seitenzahl: 484

Veröffentlichungsjahr: 2025

Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



Table of Contents

Cover

Table of Contents

Title Page

Copyright Page

Dedication Page

Introduction

Acknowledgements

PART I:

Philosophical Psychology

1 The Nature of the Mind

2 The Nature of Our Body and the Mind/Body Relation

3 What Is Consciousness?

4 Consciousness and Experience or ‘What It Is Like to Be a Bat’ Revisited

5 Other Minds and Other People

PART II:

Epistemology

6 Knowledge

7 Belief

8 Memory

9 Imagination

10 Thinking

11 On Dreams and Dreaming

PART III:

Axiology

12 The Place of Value in a World of Facts

13 Morality and the Analysis of Moral Goodness

14 Badness, Wickedness, Evil and the Death of the Soul

15 Happiness

PART IV:

Methodology

16 On Method: Connective, Contrastive, and Contextual Analysis

Further Reading

Essay 1: The Nature of the Mind

Essay 2: The Nature of Our Body and the Mind/Body Relation

Essay 3: What Is Consciousness?

Essay 4: Consciousness and Experience or ‘What It Is Like to Be a Bat?’ Revisited

Essay 5: Other Minds and Other People

Essay 6: Knowledge

Essay 7: Belief

Essay 8: Memory

Essay 9: Imagination

Essay 10: Thinking

Essay 11: On Dreams and Dreaming

Essay 12: The Place of Value in a World of Facts

Essay 13: Morality and the Analysis of Moral Goodness

Essay 14: Badness, Wickedness, Evil and the Death of the Soul

Essay 15: Happiness

Essay 16: On Method: Connective, Contrastive, and Contextual Analysis

Index

End User License Agreement

Guide

Cover Page

Table of Contents

Title Page

Copyright Page

Dedication Page

Introduction

Acknowledgements

Begin Reading

Further Reading

Index

WILEY END USER LICENSE AGREEMENT

Pages

iii

iv

v

ix

x

xi

xii

xiii

xiv

xv

xvi

1

3

4

5

6

7

8

9

10

11

12

13

14

15

16

17

18

19

20

21

22

23

24

25

26

27

28

29

30

31

32

33

34

35

36

37

38

39

40

41

42

43

44

45

46

47

48

49

50

51

52

53

54

55

56

57

58

59

61

63

64

65

66

67

68

69

70

71

72

73

74

75

76

77

78

79

80

81

82

83

84

85

86

87

88

89

90

91

92

93

94

95

96

97

98

99

100

101

102

103

104

105

106

107

108

109

110

111

112

113

114

115

116

117

118

119

120

121

122

123

124

125

126

127

128

129

130

131

132

133

134

135

136

137

138

139

140

141

143

145

146

147

148

149

150

151

152

153

154

155

156

157

158

159

160

161

162

163

164

165

166

167

168

169

170

171

172

173

174

175

176

177

178

179

180

181

182

183

184

185

186

187

188

189

190

191

192

193

194

195

196

197

198

199

200

201

203

205

206

207

208

209

210

211

212

213

214

215

216

217

218

219

220

221

222

223

224

225

226

227

228

229

230

231

232

233

234

235

Solving, Resolving, and Dissolving Philosophical Problems

Essays in Connective, Contrastive and Contextual Analysis

P. M. S. Hacker

This edition first published 2025© 2025 John Wiley & Sons Ltd

All rights reserved, including rights for text and data mining and training of artificial intelligence technologies or similar technologies. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by law. Advice on how to obtain permission to reuse material from this title is available at http://www.wiley.com/go/permissions.

The right of P. M. S. Hacker to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with law.

Registered OfficesJohn Wiley & Sons, Inc., 111 River Street, Hoboken, NJ 07030, USAJohn Wiley & Sons Ltd, New Era House, 8 Oldlands Way, Bognor Regis, West Sussex, PO22 9NQ, UK

For details of our global editorial offices, customer services, and more information about Wiley products visit us at www.wiley.com.

Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats and by print‐on‐demand. Some content that appears in standard print versions of this book may not be available in other formats.

Trademarks: Wiley and the Wiley logo are trademarks or registered trademarks of John Wiley & Sons, Inc. and/or its affiliates in the United States and other countries and may not be used without written permission. All other trademarks are the property of their respective owners. John Wiley & Sons, Inc. is not associated with any product or vendor mentioned in this book.

Limit of Liability/Disclaimer of WarrantyWhile the publisher and authors have used their best efforts in preparing this work, they make no representations or warranties with respect to the accuracy or completeness of the contents of this work and specifically disclaim all warranties, including without limitation any implied warranties of merchantability or fitness for a particular purpose. No warranty may be created or extended by sales representatives, written sales materials or promotional statements for this work. This work is sold with the understanding that the publisher is not engaged in rendering professional services. The advice and strategies contained herein may not be suitable for your situation. You should consult with a specialist where appropriate. The fact that an organization, website, or product is referred to in this work as a citation and/or potential source of further information does not mean that the publisher and authors endorse the information or services the organization, website, or product may provide or recommendations it may make. Further, readers should be aware that websites listed in this work may have changed or disappeared between when this work was written and when it is read. Neither the publisher nor authors shall be liable for any loss of profit or any other commercial damages, including but not limited to special, incidental, consequential, or other damages.

Library of Congress Cataloging‐in‐Publication DataNames: Hacker, P. M. S. (Peter Michael Stephan), author. | John Wiley & Sons, publisher.Title: Solving, resolving, and dissolving philosophical problems : on the methodology of connective, contrastive, and contextual analysis / P. M. S. Hacker.Description: Hoboken, NJ : Wiley‐Blackwell, 2025. | Includes bibliographical references and index.Identifiers: LCCN 2024034639 (print) | LCCN 2024034640 (ebook) | ISBN 9781394278817 (paperback) | ISBN 9781394278831 (adobe pdf) | ISBN 9781394278824 (epub)Subjects: LCSH: Analysis (Philosophy). | Philosophy–Methodology.Classification: LCC B808.5 .H27 2025 (print) | LCC B808.5 (ebook) | DDC 146/.4–dc23/eng/20240905LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2024034639LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2024034640

Cover Design and Image: Nina Hacker

For

Hans Oberdiek

and

Claire Parker

Introduction

At some stage in their lives, most thoughtful people wonder about philosophical problems. Can one arrive at adulthood without questioning whether God exists, whether there is life after death, or what our existence on earth is good for? A reflective young adult can hardly fail to ask whether human life has a purpose, and if so, what it is, or to query what a good life is and how it should be lived. Many people are liable, at some time or other, to wonder what truth is, and if they succumb to the deceptive appeal of the excesses of postmodernism, they may take perverse comfort in thinking that there is no absolute truth, only your truth and my truth and the truth of the ruling classes. We are singularly ill‐equipped to handle such deep questions and to confront such dogmatic and intellectually pernicious relativism without assistance.

Great philosophers throughout the ages have struggled with them. It is not the purpose of this short book to give an account of their struggles. Such accounts are to be found in fine histories of philosophy such as Anthony Kenny’s New History of Western Philosophy. The great philosophers of the past adopted a wide variety of methods of philosophical enquiry. These different methods have been well surveyed in numerous publications and another such survey will not be essayed here, even though this is a book concerned with methodology. Indeed, it is written to advocate a particular method or interconnected set of methods for solving, resolving, or dissolving problems in philosophy. But it is a method or methods altogether distinct from the those practiced in most current university departments. This book presupposes little philosophical knowledge, but only curiosity and an open mind. It demands only a willingness to learn not doctrine but method, and the courage to suspend judgement and to challenge received ideas.

Given that we are going to be deeply concerned with method in philosophical enquiry, it might seem that we should start our investigations with a brief and uncontroversial statement of what philosophy is, as one might start a book on methodology in biochemistry with a clear, brief characterization of what exactly biochemistry is. But to try to characterize philosophical problems on the first page of a book concerned with philosophical method would be to rush in prematurely, leaving the angels behind. There are few problems more controversial in philosophy than the problem of what precisely philosophy is and what exactly a philosophical problem is. That itself is an interesting fact, for no other academic subject suffers from such omphaloskepsis (navel‐gazing). Physicists do not write lengthy and controversial papers on what physics is. Chemists and biologists do not write passion‐provoking books on what chemistry or biology are. Nor do economists or experimental psychologists quarrel over what their subject is, as opposed to how to do it. But what philosophy is, is a perennial philosophical problem. It will not be confronted now, although by the end of this book something of an answer will have emerged.

My purpose in this book is not only to try, by considered argument, to demonstrate to readers what they should think on some deep philosophical problems, but also to show them how they should think productively. Indeed, my intent is to do the former by means of the latter. I have selected fifteen perennial philosophical topics for scrutiny (Essays 1–15). Many alternatives might well have been chosen, but these struck me as particularly revealing. They should be of concern to any thinking person, and the results of the methods of enquiry are often both striking and unexpected. The essays fall into three groups: (i) the nature of the mind, the mind/body problem and the nature of consciousness, our knowledge of other people; (ii) epistemological problems concerning knowledge, belief, memory, imagination, thinking and dreaming; (iii) the roots of value, the nature of moral goodness, and the differentiation between the bad, the wicked, and the evil; and so as not to end on so grim a subject: the characterization of human happiness.

Each of these essays (with the exception of the one on dreaming) gives a highly compressed overview (between 11 and 13 pages) of a very much longer and far more comprehensive discussion of these topics in a tetralogy on human nature that I published with Wiley/Blackwell between 2007 and 2021: Human Nature: The Categorial Framework (2007), The Intellectual Powers (2013), The Passions (2018), and The Moral Powers (2021). My purpose in the tetralogy was to provide a comprehensive survey of all the characterizing conceptual connections of the salient features of human nature that I had come across in fifty years of philosophical study. It was intended to be, among other things, a repository of logico‐grammatical truths pertinent to the philosophical investigation of human nature (what Kant called ‘philosophical anthropology’ and the British called ‘the moral sciences’). For it seemed to me absurd that these should be lost from generation to generation and have to be laboriously discovered afresh. To be sure, philosophy is not a progressive subject: there are advances and regresses, but that does not mean that we cannot salvage enduring insights from the wreckage and pass them on to future generations. The tetralogy employed the methods I had learnt from my betters and from decades of study and writing, but it was not a treatise on method. It was a treatise on human nature.

This short book, however, is a treatise on method. But method before practice is like recipes before dinner. The strategy of the book is to display the methods in practice before examining the theory of the practice. But as the various logico‐linguistic techniques are employed in the essays, their use and the fruitfulness of their use are recurrently emphasized. There is a degree of deliberate repetition in the methodological comments – one cannot teach a technique, such as playing the piano, without reiteration. A comprehensive overview and systematic defence of the methods of connective, contrastive, and contextual analysis is given only in the long concluding Essay 16. There, criticisms are rebutted, misconstruals are corrected, and misunderstandings are clarified.

It will quickly be noticed that this book lacks all the usual critical apparatus characteristic of academia. There are hardly any footnotes sprouting at the bottom of the page, very few contemporary philosophers are mentioned and fewer still are explicitly confronted in the thrust and riposte of debate. This is no coincidence. Everything has been pared away in the interests of clarity of ideas and transparency of argument. Who actually holds the ideas among our contemporaries and how many variations on a given idea can be found in what goes by the name of the ‘literature’ is of little moment for my purposes. What matters are the ideas, perspicuously displayed. Any competent philosopher can build yet more epicycles on erroneous orbits of misplaced planets – but these are of mere scholastic, not substantive, interest. Similarly, who advances a given misguided argument in the bustle of today’s philosophical bourse is irrelevant to the display of its invalidity or inadequacy in a book on methodology (a Prioritätstreit [priority dispute] over truth may be forgivable, but surely not over error). One consequence of this economy of expression is that the discussions are often extremely condensed. Each essay should be read slowly and more than once.

The methods advocated are at odds with much philosophical practice in the Anglophone world today. It is perhaps an exaggeration to assert that contemporary students of philosophy, both undergraduates and graduates, are instructed to approach any given philosophical problem by reading the last decade of journal publications that discuss it, and perhaps a handful of chapters or extracts from current books. But it is not far from the truth, as is exhibited in current philosophical journals, companions to philosophy and philosophical handbooks, Wikipedia, and encyclopedias of the Internet beloved by students of philosophy and philosophical journalists. Are these not the official repositories of human knowledge in the twenty‐first century? This popular pedagogic principle of economy of effort is not arbitrary, only parochial, cleaving to passing fashions that will be obsolete within a decade or two. It is based on the natural sciences, the general form of which is progress. No physicist is likely to be told to read Galileo or Copernicus for an essay, and no biologist is instructed to read Galen or Vesalius for a tutorial. Teamwork, led by a powerful professoriate, with incessant bureaucratic demands for immediate research results characterizes contemporary methods of scientific research at universities. Following this example is eroding philosophical excellence in the academy.

The pedagogical emulation of the sciences in philosophical method guarantees:

the domination of current philosophical doctrines and the reinforcing of current preconceptions and prejudices

proliferation of ‐isms and ‐ists

the relative neglect of twenty‐five centuries of struggle by philosophers of genius with problems many of which differ but little from those with which we currently engage.

the assimilation into philosophy of methods of research alien to the nature of the subject and inimical to the achievement of its intellectual goals – no matter how satisfactory for university bureaucracies and international measures of quality control in terms of publications and citations.

The domination of current philosophical practices and products is a consequence of two features. The first is the increasing centralization of education both at governmental level and at the level of university administration, and the growth of power of the university professoriate and pedagogical bureaucracies. This corporatism penalizes independent thought by students and junior faculty alike. It ensures that few will have the desire, let alone the courage, to cut across the grain of current prejudices. The student of philosophy, from undergraduate to faculty, is not guided by the problems, but by current thinking on the problems with all its preconceptions.

The second is the belief in philosophical progress on the model of scientific progress. Philosophy is seen as a battleground of doctrines. Only time (and perhaps science), it is thought, will tell which ones will triumph.

It is this, in part, that leads to the proliferation of ‐isms and ‐ists. It is they that guarantee blinkered thought. For ‐isms and ‐ists are ready‐mades designed to save one the trouble of thinking for oneself and to prevent one from reading a text with an open mind. It makes teaching easy, for one need not teach students how to think for themselves and how to confront a question by themselves, but only to opt for a party. The primary question then becomes: what sort of ‐ist should I be: a functionalist or a reductionist, a realist or an anti‐realist, an internalist or an externalist, a representationalist or an idealist … or some other ‐ist?

Because the mainstream of anglophone philosophy today is mesmerized by science and intoxicated by theory, and because it conceives of philosophy as progressive on the model of the natural sciences, history of philosophy (with the exception of ancient philosophy) is to a large extent relegated to the sidelines. This is the obverse face of the science‐emulating assumption that the research of the last decade already incorporates all that is currently known, and therefore this alone is worth studying. But philosophical problems are not akin to problems in the empirical sciences that are to be solved by observation, theory construction and confirmation or infirmation. There is much more to be learnt from studying the great thinkers of the past who tussled with problems similar to, if not identical with, those we engage with than from reading all the articles written on a given problem in the last decade. No one writing in current philosophy journals is as deep a thinker as Plato or Aristotle, Aquinas or Scotus, Descartes or Spinoza, Hobbes or Locke, Hume or Kant. The distinctions they drew, for example between psuchē and body, may still be of value to us. Their lack of some of our distinctions, for example, between the voluntary and the intentional, may illuminate the value of our distinctions. Distinctions they drew that are fundamentally different from ours, for example between form and matter, may free us from the prejudice that our current distinctions are the only correct ones, or are the best ones.

Studying the way past geniuses engaged with problems similar to ours helps to give us a measured distance from the way we currently handle the problems, and so a sharpened awareness of our own parochialism. The distance of centuries between their works and ours makes it easier to pin down their fundamental presuppositions and to question them. That in turn makes it easier for us to lay bare our own presuppositions and to challenge them. If it is sometimes relatively easy for us to apprehend what is awry with widely accepted ideas among philosophers of the past, that should not encourage us to pass them by with a sense of superiority. On the contrary, it should drive us to investigate, for example, how great thinkers such as Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, Locke, Berkeley, or Hume could have been so taken with their New Way of Ideas that the philosophical vision of their culture was, as it were, mesmerized for one hundred and fifty years. Only by discovering this can we learn anything from their great mistakes. We can rest assured that had we, per impossibile, been philosophers during their times, we too would have walked blindly along the Way of Ideas without any awareness of its irremediable defects. This investigation into the deep roots of their errors may in turn make it easier for us to search for similarly unquestioned philosophical presuppositions of our times.

Philosophers should greet each other, Wittgenstein suggested, with the exclamation, ‘Take your time!’ Faced with a philosophical problem, we are prone to rush to answer it. And if we are blinkered by current ‐isms and ‐ists, we shall expend much effort elaborating how a realist would answer the question and how an anti‐realist would do so, how an absolutist would handle it and how a relativist would, how an internalist would cope with it and how an externalist. But that is futile. One must rather take things slowly. First, investigate the question: how does the problem arise in the first place? What needs would an answer serve? What is the point and purpose of asking the question? What are its presuppositions? Is it a good question at all? In short, challenge the question, rather than rushing to answer it.

Some fundamental philosophical controversies persist for many centuries. A wise methodological principle is that when faced by a perennial debate between two different schools of philosophy with respect to some great matter, one should not examine the arguments on both sides and plumb for the strongest. If that could have solved matters, they would have been solved many a century ago. Rather, one should investigate what is agreed upon by all participants in the debate, and challenge that. It is the agreed presuppositions, very often the unmentioned agreed presuppositions, that may hold the key to the solution.

Many striking and unexpected conclusions result from the use of the manifold methods and techniques of connective, contrastive, and contextual logico‐linguistic analysis. These conclusions stand in diametric opposition to many contemporary views, doctrines, and theories. I hope that they will be sufficiently convincing and appealing to encourage readers to eschew the colourful banners waving in the marketplace of ideas and to fend for themselves. Equipped with the methods, they will be able to follow Kant’s advice, Sapere aude, and have the courage to think for themselves.

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to many dear friends and colleagues who encouraged me in the writing of this book. Their moral support has been heart‐warming and their judicious criticisms have saved me from many an error. Hanoch Ben‐Yami, John Cottingham, Lassi Jakola, Anthony Kenny, Juan Pascual, Severin Schroeder, and Gabriele Taylor all read one or more of the essays. Their comments were invaluable.

I am grateful to attendants at my final two courses of lectures at Oxford University on Wednesday afternoons in the Radcliffe Philosophy Department lecture room in Michaelmas Term 2023 and Hilary Term 2024. Their questions were stimulating and challenging.

I owe a special debt of gratitude to Hans Oberdiek and Claire Parker who read and commented in detail on every essay. Their demand for clarity was exemplary, their criticisms invaluable, and their suggestions unfailingly constructive. The very idea of the book was Hans’s. I would not have been able to bring it to fruition but for Claire’s constant support and enthusiasm.

PART IPhilosophical Psychology

1The Nature of the Mind

“The genuine philosophy of the human mind, is in so low a state, and has so many enemies, that, I apprehend those who would make any improvement in it must, for a time, build with one hand and hold a weapon with the other.”

Thomas Reid, Correspondence, letter toJames Gregory, 6 August 1783

1. That human beings have a mind is news from nowhere, but what it is that one has when one has a mind is perplexing. Am I identical with my mind or is the mind a part of me – the thinking part, perhaps? When I speak of my mind, am I speaking of myself or of my self? The mind is something I have and so, it seems, is the self, for am I not required to be true to mine own self? Is the mind identical to the self or distinct from it? Where does the soul stand? Do human beings have a soul, or is that an obsolete theological notion? If not, is the soul identical to the mind or distinct from it? And how is the soul related to the self? Of course, I also have a brain. If I have a mind, a soul, a self, and a brain, what is this ‘I’ that has these things?

Some of these items, things or entities can be readily disposed of. Their entitative claims are altogether bogus. Incidentally, beware of the pretentious term ‘entity’ – it sounds impressive, but it is merely an Anglicized cognate of the Latin ens, which means no more than the humble Anglo‐Saxon ‘thing’. So, what sort of thing is a self? Indeed, is it a thing at all? How should we investigate the matter? Certainly not by surveying all the pronouncements of philosophers on the self nor by scrutinizing all their philosophical theories. Philosophers have the difficult task of exploring the bounds of sense, of clarifying the manifold distinctions between sense and nonsense, of showing the multiple forms of nonsense – and by ‘nonsense’ I do not mean rubbish, I mean forms of words and utterance that for one reason or another do not make sense, that transgress the bounds of sense even though they do not seem to do so. Since philosophers, or at any rate analytic philosophers, spend much of their time crawling, with a magnifying glass, along the boundaries that separate sense from nonsense, it is not surprising that they often find themselves, the descriptions they offer, and the theories they advance, on the wrong side of the boundary. When faced with a problematic notion, such as the self, the I, the soul, the mind, we should not begin our investigations with a survey of the prevalent philosophical theories and their argumentative support and then endeavour to choose the most plausible one or, perhaps, more radically, come to repudiate the very idea of theory in philosophy as a deep misconception. That can come much later, when we have found our own way. Only then may we be in a position critically to evaluate the doctrines and theories of past and present philosophers. We should start by wiping the board clean and examining the raw data.

What are the raw data for a philosophical problem or puzzle if not the past theories? Philosophical problems and puzzles, as we shall show again and again in the course of these essays, are conceptual problems and puzzles. They are rooted in our conceptual scheme, in the ways in which we conceive of things and features of things in the world we inhabit, in our experiences of them and in our thoughts about them. Our conceptual scheme is expressed by the language we employ in our discourse and articulate reflections. Indeed, our language is inextricably implicated in the creation and moulding of our concepts. So the raw data for critical reflection are the uses of words, and they are tabulated in our dictionaries. So our first stop of call is the complete Oxford English Dictionary, with its itemization of usage and plethora of examples of each use, as well as lexicographical history and etymology. This will not give us any answers to our conceptual questions, but it will provide us with the raw data upon which to work.

2. If we look to the Oxford English Dictionary for elaboration of meanings, we find that the noun ‘mind’ is said to signify the faculty of consciousness and thought which enables human beings to be aware of the world and of their experiences. This connection between the mind and consciousness was Cartesian. The concept of consciousness was of seventeenth‐century origin and defining the mind in terms of being conscious of something (transitive consciousness) was a radical innovation that, as is patent from the Oxford English Dictionary, is with us to this day. But the concept of mind is very much older than the seventeenth century and had previously been conceived in terms of the capacity for rationality. Only philosophical investigation can disclose which is the more coherent and illuminating conception of the mind and of human nature.

A first step towards elucidation is to examine English usage, perspicuously laid out in the Oxford English Dictionary, to see what light it sheds on our concept of mind. What is most striking is the multitude of English idioms that make use of the word ‘mind’, for example, to have a keen mind, an open mind, to close one’s mind to, to clear one’s mind, to call to mind, for something to slip out of one’s mind, to have a mind to do something, to be in half a mind to do something, to be in two minds whether to do something, to make up one’s mind, to change one’s mind, to have something in mind, and many more. Rather than dismissing this as language‐local idiom, which it is, and dismissing it as of no philosophical importance, which it isn’t, we should seek for patterns in usage that illuminate our concept of mind and provide grounds for connective and contrastive analysis.

3. The manifold idioms are evident in daily discourse. To get an overall picture of their point and purpose will be illuminating for elucidating the concept of mind. For it is easy to arrange the various idioms in six clusters or focal points, although they are not neat, non‐overlapping clusters and they are not exhaustive either. It is also easy to paraphrase each ‘mind’‐incorporating idiom into an equivalent phrase in which the word ‘mind’ does not occur. One cluster is focused on memory and remembering. To hold or keep something in mind is to ensure that one won’t overlook it; to bear something in mind is to remember it so that one will be able to take it into account. To call or bring something to mind is to recollect it. For something to be, go, pass out of, or slip out of mind is for it to be forgotten. To cast one’s mind back is to try to remember, and to be absent‐minded is to be forgetful or inattentive.

A second focal point is thought and thinking. To have a thought cross one’s mind or for an idea to come to mind is for something to occur to one. For something to lurk at the back of one’s mind is to be trying without success to think of something. To turn one’s mind to something is to start thinking about it. To have something on one’s mind is to be preoccupied with it. To have a load taken off one’s mind is to be relieved of anxiously thinking about it. One’s mind is in a turmoil when one doesn’t know what to do or to think. One’s mind wanders when one cannot concentrate or attend. One’s mind goes blank when one does not know what to say and is at a loss. One has an original cast of mind when one displays originality in thought, discourse, and action.

A third cluster concerns opinion and opining. To know one’s mind is to have formed one’s opinion, and to tell or speak one’s mind is to express it. To be of one mind with another is to agree in opinion or judgement. To give someone a piece of one’s mind is to tell him harshly one’s opinion of him.

A fourth focal point is intention and intending. To be minded or to have it in mind to do something is to be inclined or to intend to do it. To have half a mind to do something is to be tempted to do it and to be in two minds whether to do something is to be undecided. To make up one’s mind is to decide and to change one’s mind is to reverse one’s decision. To have a mind of one’s own is to be independent in judgement and decision.

A further focal point is the characterization of a person’s intellect: one may have a powerful, agile, subtle, or devious mind if one is skilful, quick, and ingenious at problem solving or if one’s solutions, plans, and projects display subtlety and cunning. Other characterizations are linked to intellectual virtues and faults. One may have a tenacious, idle, judicious, indecisive mind according to the manner in which one grapples with problems.

Another cluster concerns rationality: one is of sound mind if one retains one’s rational faculties and one is out of one’s mind if one thinks, proposes, and acts irrationally. One is not in one’s right mind if one is distraught and one has lost one’s mind if one is bereft of one’s rational faculties. One may be small or petty minded if one makes a fuss over trivialities of behaviour of others, one is broad or narrow minded according to one’s receptivity to unconventional ideas and behaviour. One may have a mind like a razor or a dirty mind; one may possess peace of mind and have presence of mind.

4. Here then we can see the concept of mind at work. From this ordering of raw data one may draw important conclusions about the use of the expression ‘the mind’ in English. Of course, other languages may not have a word that corresponds exactly with ‘the mind’: German and French have to make do with a pair of expressions, namely ‘Geist’ and ‘Seele’ and ‘l’âme’ and l’esprit’ where English has the triplet ‘mind’, ‘soul’, and ‘spirit’. So their concepts are somewhat different from ours. Few languages have as wide a range of mind‐associated prepositional idioms, which may mean that English is fortunate in being able to draw distinctions absent in other languages. There is much that a philosopher can learn from the wealth of ‘mind’‐associated idioms.

First, each idiom is paraphrasable into a different equivalent expression in which the word ‘mind’ does not occur. What does this imply? It does not mean that all our talk of the mind is peculiar ‘as if’ talk of a ‘pretend entity’ or ‘pretend agent’. Our use of ‘the mind’ is not at all like our use of ‘Father Christmas’ or even ‘unicorn’ and ‘dragon’. This does not mean that our use of ‘mind’‐incorporating expressions is but a façon de parler. That would suggest that it is just a manner of speaking, akin to signing one’s letters ‘yours truly’, ‘yours faithfully’, or ‘yours sincerely’, and that would imply that in fact people don’t have minds. But, to be sure, decisive people have minds of their own, stupid people are mindless, and people who have lost their mind have lost their rational faculties. So what should we conclude? Surely this: that our idiomatic talk of human minds is a form of representation – a way of presenting human intellectual powers and their exercise in thought, volition, and action. We present possession of a wide range of intellectual powers and their exercise in the form of possession of an object, namely: the mind.

From this we can draw further conclusions. The mind is not an object, not a kind of thing or, more pretentiously, not an entity of any kind. The mind, we might say, is not a something, but it is not a nothing either. So taking the mind to be a kind of substance, as Descartes (1596–1650) did, is a mistake. The mind is neither a material substance nor an immaterial substance because it is not a substance at all. To say (correctly) that human beings have minds is a conceptual truth that characterizes human nature. It is, in effect, the expression of a rule for the use of ‘mind’ and ‘human being’ that signifies that it makes sense to ask with respect to any human being what sort of mind he has, whether he has anything on his mind, or whether he has made up his mind, and so forth. A further consequence that flows from the possibility of paraphrastic de‐reification is that when we say that that NN has a dirty mind, that he has turned his mind to such‐and‐such, and that he has changed his mind, we are not talking of one thing that is dirty, has been turned, and has changed. We are talking of one human being who tends to think sordid thoughts, who has taken up a fresh subject for reflection and concentration and has reversed a prior decision. Another important consequence is the repudiation of Thomas Reid (1710–96), who argued that the mind is ‘that in [man] which thinks, imagines, reasons, wills’, and John Stuart Mill (1806–73) who held the mind to be ‘a mysterious something that thinks and feels’. For the mind is not a something, and we don’t, by and large, speak of the mind as agential. It is not my mind that thinks, imagines, reasons or wills – it is I, this living human being. Curiously, we do speak of the mind as a patient in as much as my mind may go blank, be in a turmoil, wander – these not being acts or activities of an agent. But, to be sure, my mind does not make up its mind or change its mind since it has no mind.

5. A further consequence of our investigation thus far is that the contemporary tendency to identify the mind with the brain is mistaken. For the mind is not a kind of thing, but the brain certainly is. It is a bodily organ, about seven inches high and three pounds in weight consisting of billions of neurons and synapses. But a material object cannot be identical with something that is neither material nor an object.

In response to this objection, philosophers may shift ground and advance the idea that psychological attributes are in fact identical with brain states, processes, or events. Knowing and believing, understanding, being frightened and being cheerful, desiring and intending are all, according to some philosophers, states of mind. They are contingently identical with states of the brain.

This cannot be right. Cortical states are states of the brain, mental states are states of a human being and a human being is not a brain but has a brain. A brain may be in a sclerotic state, a human being cannot; a human being may be in an anxious state, but a brain can’t be anxious about anything. Knowing, believing, and understanding are not mental states comparable to feeling frightened, being cheerful or anxious. The latter do not persist during periods of sleep or unconsciousness (which is why ‘sleep knits up the ravell’d sleeve of care’). But one does not cease to know, believe, or understand things when one falls asleep (and one does not have to learn them afresh when one awakes). There is no such thing as being in a state of knowing (as one may be in a state of anxiety), let alone such a thing as being in a believing state or in a mental state of understanding (for further elaboration, see Essays 6 and 7). Something that is not a state cannot be identical with a state.

6. Since Descartes philosophers have struggled with the question ‘What is the mind?’ Some, like Descartes, have held that the mind (‘anima’, ‘l’âme’, ‘l’esprit’) is a substance – a persistent immaterial entity annexed to the body, but which can survive the demise of the body. Others like Locke (1632–1704) have held that the mind is a collection of perceptions and ideas unified by consciousness, connected to a human body. Yet others, like Berkeley (1685–1753), agreed with Descartes that the mind is a spiritual substance but denied that it is annexed to a material body, since he denied that there are any bodies at all. Hume agreed that there are no material substances, but argued that there are no spiritual substances either: the mind is merely a bundle of perceptions held together by causation and memory – but left it opaque how perceptions can be tied in bundles, and how causation and memory can function as binding string. To such incoherences have great thinkers been driven.

When philosophers have been struggling with a question over many centuries, giving increasingly bizarre conclusions, it seems appropriate not to add yet another theory but to challenge the question. Perhaps the question ‘What is the mind?’ is just a bad question. Why so? In part, because What is questions invite It is an answers and as our linguistic investigations suggest, the mind is not an anything. We should reject the question and replace it by another one: What has to be true of a creature for us to say of it that it has a mind? This question is more manageable.

To have a mind a creature has to be a sentient animal that has and exercises a wide range of powers to do or refrain from doing something, and the ability to acquire further powers through experience and learning. More specifically, it must acquire and then possess and exercise powers of rationality and reasonableness. A creature with a mind has the ability to reason, correctly or incorrectly, from premises to conclusions and to be sensitive (reactive) to reasons, which may be good, poor, or perverse, for thinking, feeling, and acting. Such abilities presuppose possession of a language.

Our linguistic analysis showed that talk of the mind focuses on mnemonic powers that stretch far wider than merely remembering how to do things, where certain things are, when certain events regularly occur, and so forth. It includes memory that certain things are so, that certain things happened or are going to happen (e.g. the time of the opera next week), personal memory (possession of a history and ‘autobiography’), memory of general truths (all // some // many // much // most // X‐s are Y‐s), and timeless truths (of logic or mathematics). It is patent that this requires mastery of a language incorporating logical connectives (‘not’, ‘and’, ‘or’, ‘if … then …’) and quantifiers (‘all’, ‘some’, ‘many’, ‘a few’), devices for temporal indexing and reference (now/then; earlier/later; yesterday/today/tomorrow; last year/next year), names of kinds of things, place‐referring expressions, and pronouns. This will be further discussed in Essay 8.

Possession of a mind was linked with the ability to think, correctly or incorrectly, and to form opinions, reasonable or unreasonable. A creature with a mind has the ability to reason, correctly or incorrectly, from premises to conclusion, from evidence to what it allegedly supports, to acquire information or opinion from reasoning and to retain it for future use. This too is a prerogative of language‐using creatures. Possession of a mind is equally closely connected to intention‐formation on the basis of thought and opinion. To have a mind implies possession of the powers of practical reasoning: to form intentions on the basis of what one knows and remembers and of opinions and convictions, which may be enlightened or prejudiced and bigoted. Creatures with a mind not only pursue purposes and have immediate goals, but are able to form intentions, both good and evil, long in advance of action, to modify them on the basis of new information or changing plans.

To have a mind is to possess and use powers of intellect manifest in thought, feeling and action. These are powers not of minds, but of creatures with a mind. They are not powers of brains, since brains have no intellect and there is no such thing as a brain acting for a good or poor reason, or harbouring and defending an opinion, let alone making inferences and weighing evidence. Of course, creatures with minds also have brains without which they would not have the constitutive features of having a mind. A brain is indeed necessary for any creature to have a mind, but it does not follow that the mind is the brain.

7. We have not examined the variety of theories of mind produced by philosophers throughout the ages. Plato’s Socrates (470–399 BC) is a primary font of dualism of mind and body. According to his Orphic views, a person’s soul pre‐existed its bodily incarnation and survives the death of the body – a doctrine known as metempsychosis. A different kind of dualism was advanced by Christianity and powerfully articulated by Augustine (354–430 AD). In the hands of Descartes, the primary source of substance dualism, the boundary of the mind was redrawn and the nature of the mental was transformed. Biology was reduced to physics, which concerned itself with the study of the laws of matter in motion. The limits of physics lay at the portals of the mind. The mind was conceived to be a persistent immaterial object defined by the unique attribute of thought, in an extended sense of the term that incorporates all conscious experience. It is distinct from the body, although intimately united with it in human life. The mind is in two‐way interaction with the body. It was redefined not as the rational part of human beings, but as consciousness of all thought and experience. It was held to be identical with the self or person, and to be transparent to its subject – there was nothing in the mind of which the self was unaware, and everything one was conscious of was as one was conscious of it as being. Moreover, the thoughts or experiences of which the mind consists were indubitable. The subject alone has direct knowledge of his own thoughts or experiences, which are uniquely owned by him. This conception is still with us in the contemporary idea that to have a mind is to have experience, and that to have experience is for there to be something that it is like for the subject to enjoy or undergo it. These ideas will be investigated in Essay 4.

From the point of view of the current investigation, the most important of the ancient philosophers who investigated the nature of man is Aristotle. He rejected Plato’s dualism and advanced a form of non‐reductive monism. While Plato (428/7–348/7 BC), like his teacher Socrates, conceived of the mind or soul as being embodied but surviving the death of the body, Aristotle (384–322 BC), his pupil, conceived of psuchē as a biological concept (it is commonly mistranslated as ‘soul’ which is a moral or theological concept). The psuchē is constituted by the powers of living things. All living things have a vegetative psuchē, namely the powers of metabolism, growth, and reproduction. Animals have a sensitive psuchē, since over and above their vegetative powers they have powers of sensation, perception and locomotion, desire, and aversion, as well as susceptibilities to pain, pleasure, and emotion. The rational psuchē that is distinctive of man consists, in addition to the vegetative and sensitive powers, in the further abilities to reason and to act for reasons. To have the rational psuchē is to have an intellect and will (ratiocinated desire). It is to be able to reason, to apprehend and act for reasons, to deliberate and decide on the basis of reasons for what to think, feel, and do. The Aristotelian psuchē is not a substance. It is neither identical with the animal body nor distinct from it. The psuchē stands to the body as the form of a statue to the statue of which it is the form. It makes no sense to ask whether they are one or two. Accordingly, the psuchēis not a part of a human being nor is it embodied in the human being or human body. Rather, the human body is empsuchos: informed by the psuchē. It is not causally related to the living animal, since powers are not causes of their exercise. The human psuchē is not essentially private, since I may express my thoughts and then you will know what I think, and I may share my thoughts with you. It is not transparent to its subject, since I may not realize that I know or understand something and may think I know or understand something but be mistaken. Its deliverances are not indubitable, since I may doubt whether I remember something and be unsure whether I love someone. It is not an agent, for the psuchē does not do anything, rather we do things with our psuchē, not as we do things with our hands but as we do things with our talents. Nor is the psuchē the subject of psychological attributes, since capacities, abilities and liabilities do not think, perceive, feel or form intentions.

Why is this so important? Because it shows that there is another way of conceptualizing mind‐associated phenomena that dispenses with the reification characteristic of early modern European culture and later. In this Aristotelian form of representation, the functions the concept of mind fulfils in our languages are taken over by biological powers, in particular by the sensitive and rational powers (the latter, when considered independently of the vegetative and sensitive powers, being nous). This could not be more different from the dualist form of representation and its various degenerate offspring. What is most striking, however, is that our ordinary English idiom of the mind is far closer to the Aristotelian model of the psuchē than to the Cartesian and empiricist conceptions of the mind and to contemporary psychological and neuroscientific models of the mind/brain.

8. In the opening remarks, it was noted that I can be said to have a soul, a self, and mind and a body. We have explained how to construe possession of a mind. We must now turn to demythologization and say something about the notions of the self and the I or ego.

Let us turn first to the notion of a self. The expression is indeed an ancient one. Its earliest use was simply to emphasize a nominal, as in ‘se selfa man’ which meant ‘the very man who’ or ‘the same man who’. This is the ancestor of the emphatic pronoun ‘itself’ (as in ‘the thing itself’), the reflexive pronoun ‘my (your, him, her, it) self’, and it survives in the modern adjectival use ‘the selfsame …’. It was altogether natural that the reflexive pronoun should evolve into an independent nominal and also become used to signify aspects of a person, hence someone’s nature, character, physical constitution or appearance at different times. Hence: ‘one’s former (or ‘later’) self’, ‘being or looking one’s old self again’ (after illness). Side by side with this diachronic use emerged a use to signify synchronic aspects of a person, as in ‘his better self’, ‘her true self’, ‘one’s natural self’. But it was an egregious error of seventeenth‐century philosophers to start using this harmless four‐letter word to signify some thing within a human being which a person essentially is, namely ‘a self’. For it is a logical truth that nothing can be identical with a part of itself or an aspect of itself. I should indeed be true to mine own self, to the better and most fundamental aspects of myself, but I am not a self and I don’t have a thing within me that is called ‘a self’.

Similar arguments apply to talk of ‘the “I”’. The confusion that this grammatical aberration generates is only masked, but not reduced by Latinization into ‘the Ego’. ‘I’ is a first‐person pronoun. It is not a noun and cannot licitly take either a definite or indefinite article. There is no such thing as ‘an I’, any more than there is such a thing as ‘a he’, ‘a she’, or ‘an it’. It was a misfortune, and an unnecessary one to boot, that Freud used these malformed expressions (‘das Ich’ and ‘das es’ (unfortunately translated as ‘the Ego’ and ‘the Id’)) to speak of aspects of the human personality. ‘I’ is a pronoun. Unlike the pronouns ‘he’, ‘she’, and ‘it’, it is not a referring expression. In this respect, it is more akin to ‘now’ and ‘here’, rather than to ‘then’ and ‘there’. Construed as a referring expression, it seems to be a miraculous one, for it seems immune to referential failure and to misidentification. But this is an illusion. It is not like an arrow that always hits its target, but like an arrow stuck in the wall around which one can always draw a circle. It is akin to the point of origin of our system of pointing (our deictic system) and not akin to points on the graph that are indicated by the other personal pronouns. Its primary role is to index an utterance. One commonly uses it to speak about oneself, but one does not thereby identify oneself – rather it enables one’s audience to identify of whom one is speaking. Unlike the other singular personal pronouns, it has no anaphoric use to refer to someone already mentioned. It is not a referring expression, and it certainly does not refer to something called ‘a self’. That it can be used in silent soliloquy does not show that it refers to a self, but only that one is thinking about oneself. Of course, it is used by human beings who are subjects of experience. It has a use in ascribing experiences to oneself, but not to ascribe experiences to one’s self. It is used in speaking of oneself, but not in speaking of one’s self.

2The Nature of Our Body and the Mind/Body Relation

1. In the previous essay the Aristotelian notion of the psuchē – misleadingly translated as ‘soul’ – was introduced. It is a biological concept, not a theological or moral concept. It signifies the distinctive powers of macro‐biological living things. It differentiates the characteristic powers of the plant kingdom, of the kingdom of living animals, and of mankind. Hence Aristotle writes of the vegetative psuchē of plants, the sensitive (animate) psuchē of non‐human animals, and the rational psuchē that is unique to human beings. Plants have only a vegetative psuchē. Their distinctive powers are to metabolize, to grow, to produce seed and multiply. Animals likewise have a vegetative psuchē, but in addition to their powers of metabolizing, growth, and reproduction, they have a sensitive psuchē, that is to say: senses by means of which they can apprehend their environment and feel sensations in their body, they have desires, they are self‐moving and pursue goals. Human beings alone also possess a rational psuchē, that is: the power to reason from premises to a conclusion and sensitivity to reasons for thinking, feeling, and acting. Human beings alone have the species‐characteristic of possession of an intellect (to which Aristotle refers as nous). Note that the psuchē is not an agent that acts, any more than a human being’s ability to read is an agent. But a reader exercises his ability to read whenever he reads a text. So too, a living being uses its psuchē whenever it exercises its characteristic powers and abilities. One uses one’s psuchē not in the sense in which one uses one’s legs to walk, but in the sense in which one uses one’s talents to do skilful things.

One important aspect of the Aristotelian form of representation of human powers is that the relation between the psuchē and the human body is not problematized. How my psuchē is related to my body is no more puzzling than the question of how my height or weight are related to my body. They are, as Aristotle might put it, of the body, not relations to the body. The psuchē, being an array of distinctive animate powers, is not a relatum in a binary relation. My ability to metabolize, to perceive and to move, to think and to act for reasons, do not stand in a relation to me: they are attributes of mine. This puts Aristotle in firm opposition to the dualist views of his teacher Plato, who conceived of the mind or soul as an enduring being that is embodied in a living human but pre‐existed its embodiment and survives after death. It also put Aristotle in opposition to the subsequent Christian view of a human being as a composite of body and soul, whose soul survives death. For Christian Platonists, such as St Augustine, the soul stands in a relation to the body, in as much as it is embodied