The Group Mind
The Group Mind PREFACEPART ICHAPTER ICHAPTER IICHAPTER IIICHAPTER IVCHAPTER VPART IICHAPTER VICHAPTER VIICHAPTER VIIICHAPTER IXCHAPTER XCHAPTER XICHAPTER XIICHAPTER XIIIPART IIICHAPTER XIVCHAPTER XVCHAPTER XVICHAPTER XVIICHAPTER XVIIICHAPTER XIXCHAPTER XXFOOTNOTESCopyright
The Group Mind
William McDougall
PREFACE
In this book I have sketched the principles of the mental
life of groups and have made a rough attempt to apply these
principles to the understanding of the life of nations. I have had
the substance of the book in the form of lecture notes for some
years, but have long hesitated to publish it. I have been held
back, partly by my sense of the magnitude and difficulty of the
subject and the inadequacy of my own preparation for dealing with
it, partly because I wished to build upon a firm foundation of
generally accepted principles of human nature.Some fifteen years ago I projected a complete treatise on
Social Psychology which would have comprised the substance of the
present volume. I was prevented from carrying out the ambitious
scheme, partly by the difficulty of finding a publisher, partly by
my increasing sense of the lack of any generally accepted or
acceptable account of the constitution of human nature. I found it
necessary to attempt to provide such a foundation, and in 1908
published myIntroduction to Social
Psychology. That book has enjoyed a certain
popular success. But it was more novel, more revolutionary, than I
had supposed when writing it; and my hope that it would rapidly be
accepted by my colleagues as in the main a true account of the
fundamentals of human nature has not been realised.All this part of psychology labours under the great
difficulty that the worker in it cannot, like other men of science,
publish his conclusions as discoveries which will necessarily be
accepted by any persons competent to judge. He can only state his
conclusions and his reasonings and hope that they may gradually
gain the general approval of his colleagues. For to the obscure
questions of fact with which he deals it is in the nature of things
impossible to return answers supported by indisputable experimental
proofs. In this field the evidence of an author’s approximation
towards truth can consist only in his success in gradually
persuading competent opinion of the value of his views. My sketch
of the fundamentals of human nature can hardly claim even that
degree of success which would be constituted by an active criticism
and discussion of it in competent quarters. Yet there are not
wanting indications that opinion is turning slowly towards the
acceptance of some such doctrine as I then outlined. Especially the
development of psycho-pathology, stimulated so greatly by the
esoteric dogmas of the Freudian school, points in this direction.
The only test and verification to which any scheme of human nature
can be submitted is the application of it to practice in the
elucidation of the concrete phenomena of human life and in the
control and direction of conduct, especially in the two great
fields of medicine and education. And I have been much encouraged
by finding that some workers in both of these fields have found my
scheme of use in their practice and have even, in some few cases,
given it a cordial general approval. But group psychology is itself
one of the fields in which such testing and verification must be
sought. And I have decided to delay no longer in attempting to
bring my scheme to this test. I am also impelled to venture on what
may appear to be premature publication by the fact that five of the
best years of my life have been wholly given up to military service
and the practical problems of psycho-therapy, and by the reflection
that the years of a man’s life are numbered and that, even though I
should delay yet another fifteen years, I might find that I had
made but little progress towards securing the firm foundation I
desired.It may seem to some minds astonishing that I should now admit
that the substance of this book was committed to writing before the
Great War; for that war is supposed by some to have revolutionised
all our ideas of human nature and of national life. But the war has
given me little reason to add to or to change what I had written.
This may be either because I am too old to learn, or because what I
had written was in the main true; and I am naturally disposed to
accept the second explanation.I wish to make it clear to any would-be reader of this volume
that it is a sequel to myIntroduction to Social
Psychology, that it builds upon that book and
assumes that the reader is acquainted with it. That former volume
has been criticised as an attempted outline ofSocial Psychology. One critic remarks
that it may be good psychology, but it is very little social;
another wittily says “Mr McDougall, while giving a full account of
the genesis of instincts that act in society, hardly shows how they
issue into society. He seems to do a great deal of packing in
preparation for a journey on which he never starts.” The last
sentence exactly describes the book. I found myself, like so many
of my predecessors and contemporaries, about to start on a voyage
of exploration of societies with an empty trunk, or at least with
one very inadequately supplied with the things essential for
successful travelling. I decided to avoid the usual practice of
starting without impedimenta and of picking up or inventing bits of
make-shift equipment as each emergency arose; I would pack my trunk
carefully before starting. And now although my fellow travellers
have not entirely approved my outfit, I have launched out to put it
to the test; and I cannot hope that my readers will follow me if
they have not at their command a similar outfit—namely, a similar
view of the constitution of human nature.I would gratefully confess that the resolve to go forward
without a further long period of preparation has been made possible
for me largely by the encouragement I have had from the recently
published work of Dr James Drever,Instinct in
Man. For the author of that work has carefully
studied the most fundamental part of mySocial
Psychology, in the light of his wide knowledge
of the cognate literature, and has found it to be in the main
acceptable.The title and much of the substance of the present volume
might lead a hasty reader to suppose that I am influenced by, or
even in sympathy with, the political philosophy associated with
German ‘idealism.’ I would, therefore, take this opportunity both
to prevent any such erroneous inference and to indicate my attitude
towards that system of thought in plainer language than it seemed
possible to use before the war. I have argued that we may properly
speak of a group mind, and that each of the most developed nations
of the present time may be regarded as in process of developing a
group mind. This must lay me open to the suspicion of favouring the
political philosophy which makes of the state a super-individual
and semi-divine person before whom all men must bow down,
renouncing their claims to freedom of judgment and action; the
political philosophy in short of German ‘idealism,’ which derives
in the main from Hegel, which has been so ably represented in this
country by Dr Bosanquet, which has exerted so great an influence at
Oxford, and which in my opinion is as detrimental to honest and
clear thinking as it has proved to be destructive of political
morality in its native country. I am relieved of the necessity of
attempting to justify these severe strictures by the recent
publication ofThe Metaphysical Theory of the
Stateby Prof. L. T. Hobhouse. In that volume
Prof. Hobhouse has subjected the political philosophy of German
‘idealism,’ and especially Dr Bosanquet’s presentation of it, to a
criticism which, as it seems to me, should suffice to expose the
hollowness of its claims to all men for all time; and I cannot
better define my own attitude towards it than by expressing the
completeness of my sympathy with the searching criticism of Mr
Hobhouse’s essay. In my youth I was misled into supposing that the
Germans were the possessors of a peculiar wisdom; and I have spent
a large part of my life in discovering, in one field of science
after another, that I was mistaken. I can always read the works of
some German philosophers, especially those of Hermann Lotze, with
admiration and profit; but I have no longer any desire to contend
with the great systems of ‘idealism,’ and I think it a cruel waste
that the best years of the lives of many young men should be spent
struggling with the obscure phrases in which Kant sought to express
his profound and subtle thought. My first scientific effort was to
find evidence in support of a new hypothesis of muscular
contraction; and, in working through the various German theories, I
was dismayed by their lack of clear mechanical conceptions. My next
venture was in the physiology of vision, a branch of science which
had become almost exclusively German. Starting with a prepossession
in favour of one of the dominant German theories, I soon reached
the conclusion that the two German leaders in this field, Helmholtz
and Hering, with their hosts of disciples, had, in spite of much
admirable detailed work, added little of value and much confusion
to the theory of vision left us by a great Englishman,—namely,
Thomas Young; and in a long series of papers I endeavoured to
restate and supplement Young’s theory. Advancing into the field of
physiological psychology, I attacked the ponderous volumes of Wundt
with enthusiasm; only to find that his physiology of the nervous
system was a tissue of unacceptable hypotheses and that he failed
to connect it in any profitable manner with his questionable
psychology. And, finding even less satisfaction in such works as
Ziehen’sPhysiologische Psychologie, with its crude materialism and associationism, or in the
dogmatic speculations of Verworn, I published my own small attempt
to bring psychology into fruitful relations with the physiology of
the nervous system. This brought me up against the great problem of
the relations between mind and body; and, having found that, in
this sphere, German ‘idealism’ was pragmatically indistinguishable
from thorough-going materialism, and that those Germans who claimed
to reconcile the two did not really rise much above the level of
Ernst Haeckel’s wild flounderings, I published myHistory and Defense of Animism. And in
this field, though I found much to admire in the writings of Lotze,
I derived most encouragement and stimulus from Prof. Bergson. In
working at the foundations of human nature, I found little help in
German psychology, and more in French books, especially in those of
Prof. Ribot. In psycho-pathology I seemed to find that the claims
of the German and Austrian schools were far outweighed by those of
the French writers, especially of Prof. Janet. So now, in attacking
the problems of the mental life of societies, I have found little
help from German psychology or sociology, from the elaborations of
Wundt’sVölkerpsychologieor the
ponderosities of Schäffle, and still less from the ‘idealist’
philosophy of politics. In this field also it is French authors
from whom I have learnt most and with whom I find myself most in
sympathy, especially MM. Fouillée, Boutmy, Tarde, and Demolins;
though I would not be thought to hold in low esteem the works of
many English and American authors, notably those of Buckle,
Bagehot, Maine, Lecky, Lowell, and of many others, to some of which
I have made reference in the chapters of this book.I have striven to make this a strictly scientific work,
rather than a philosophical one; that is to say, I have tried to
ascertain and state the facts and principles of social life as it
is and has been, without expressing my opinion as to what it should
be. But, in order further to guard myself against the implications
attached by German ‘idealism’ to the notion of a collective mind, I
wish to state that politically my sympathies are with individualism
and internationalism, although I have, I think, fully recognised
the great and necessary part played in human life by the Group
Spirit and by that special form of it which we now call
‘Nationalism.’I know well that those of my readers whose sympathies are
with Collectivism, Syndicalism, or Socialism in any of its various
forms will detect in this book the cloven foot of individualism and
leanings towards the aristocratic principle. I know also that many
others will reproach me with giving countenance to communistic and
ultra-democratic tendencies. I would, therefore, point out
explicitly at the outset that, if this book affords justification
for any normative doctrine or ideal, it is for one which would aim
at a synthesis of the principles of individualism and communism, of
aristocracy and democracy, of self-realization and of service to
the community. I can best express this ideal in the wise words of
Mr F. H. Bradley, which I extract from his famous essay on ‘My
Station and its Duties.’ “The individual’s consciousness of himself
is inseparable from the knowing himself as an organ of the whole;
... for his nature now is not distinct from his ‘artificial self.’
He is related to the living moral system not as to a foreign body;
his relation to it is ‘too inward even for faith,’ since faith
implies a certain separation. It is no other-world that he can not
see but must trust to; he feels himself in it, and it in him; ...
the belief in this real moral organism is the one solution of
ethical problems. It breaks down the antithesis of despotism and
individualism; it denies them, while it preserves the truth of
both. The truth of individualism is saved, because, unless we have
intense life and self-consciousness in the members of the state,
the whole state is ossified. The truth of despotism is saved,
because, unless the member realizes the whole by and in himself, he
fails to reach his own individuality. Considered in the main, the
best communities are those which have the best men for their
members, and the best men are the members of the best
communities.... The two problems of the best man and best state are
two sides, two distinguishable aspects of the one problem, how to
realize in human nature the perfect unity of homogeneity and
specification; and when we see that each of these without the other
is unreal, then we see that (speaking in general) the welfare of
the state and the welfare of its individuals are questions which it
is mistaken and ruinous to separate. Personal morality and
political and social institutions can not exist apart, and (in
general) the better the one the better the other. The community is
moral, because it realizes personal morality; personal morality is
moral, because and in so far as it realizes the moral
whole.”Since correcting the proofs of this volume I have become
acquainted with two recent books whose teaching is so closely in
harmony with my own that I wish to direct my readers’ attention to
them. One is Sir Martin Conway’sThe Crowd in
Peace and War, which contains many valuable
illustrations of group life. The other is Miss M. P.
Follett’sThe New State; Group Organization the
Solution of Popular Government, which expounds
the principles and advantages of collective deliberation with
vigour and insight.I am under much obligation to the general editor of this
series, Prof. G. Dawes Hicks. He has read the proofs of my book,
and has helped me greatly with many suggestions; but he has, of
course, no responsibility for the views expressed in
it.
PART I
GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF COLLECTIVE PSYCHOLOGY
CHAPTER I
INTRODUCTIONThe Province of Collective PsychologyTo define exactly the relations of the several special
sciences is a task which can never be completely achieved so long
as these sciences continue to grow and change. It is a peculiarly
difficult task in respect of the biological sciences, because we
have not yet reached general agreement as to the fundamental
conceptions which these sciences should employ. To illustrate this
difficulty I need only refer to a recent symposium of the
Aristotelian Society in which a number of distinguished
philosophers and biologists discussed the question “Are physical,
biological and psychological categories irreducible?” The
discussion revealed extreme differences of opinion, and failed to
bring the disputants nearer to a common view. The difficulty is
still greater in respect of the human sciences—anthropology,
psychology, ethics, politics, economics, sociology, and the rest;
and it is not to be hoped that any general agreement on this
difficult question will be reached in the near future. Yet it seems
worth while that each writer who aspires to break new ground in any
part of this field of inquiry should endeavour to make clear to
himself and others his conception of the relations of that part to
the rest of the field. It is, then, in no dogmatic spirit, or with
any belief in the finality of the position assigned to my topic,
that I venture the following definition of the province of
psychology with which this book is concerned.I have chosen the title, “The Group Mind,” after some
hesitation in favour of the alternative, “Collective Psychology.”
The latter has the advantage that it has already been used by
several continental authors, more especially French and Italian
psychologists. But the title I have chosen is, I think, more
distinctively English in quality and denotes more clearly the topic
that I desire to discuss.An alternative and not inappropriate title would have been
“An Outline of Social Psychology”; but two reasons prevented the
adoption of this. First, myIntroduction to Social
Psychologyhas become generally known by the
abbreviated titleSocial Psychology. This was an unforeseen result and unfortunate designation;
for, as I have explained in the Preface to the present volume, that
other work was designed merely as a propaedeutic; it aimed merely
at clearing the ground and laying the foundations for Social
Psychology, while leaving the topic itself for subsequent
treatment. Secondly, I conceive Group Psychology to be a part only,
though a very large part, of the total field of Social Psychology;
for, while the former has to deal only with the life of groups, the
latter has also to describe and account for the influence of the
group on the growth and activities of the individual. This is the
most concrete part of psychology and naturally comes last in the
order of development of the science; for, like other sciences,
psychology began with the most abstract notions, the forms of
activity of mind in general, and, by the aid of the abstract
conceptions achieved by the earlier workers, progresses to the
consideration of more concrete problems, the problems presented by
actual living persons in all their inexhaustible richness and
complexity.Until the later decades of the nineteenth century, psychology
continued to concern itself almost exclusively with the mind of man
conceived in an abstract fashion, not as the mind of any particular
individual, but as the mind of a representative individual
considered in abstraction from his social settings as something
given to our contemplation fully formed and complete.Two important changes of modern thought have shown the
necessity of a more concrete treatment of psychological problems.
The first has been the coming into prominence of the problems of
genesis which, although not originated by Darwin, received so great
an impetus from his work. The second has been the increasing
realisation of the need for a more synthetic treatment of all
fields of science, the realisation that analysis alone carries us
ever farther away from concrete problems and leads only to a system
of abstract conceptions which are very remote from reality, however
useful they may prove in the physical sciences. The biological and
the human sciences especially have been profoundly affected by
these two changes of modern thought. As Theodore Merz has so well
shown in the fourth volume of his monumental work[1], the need has been increasingly
felt of thevue d’ensemble, of
the synthetic mode of regarding organisms, men, and institutions,
not as single things, self-contained and complete in themselves,
but as merely nodes or meeting points of all the forces of the
world acting and reacting in unlimited time and space.Psychology was, then, until recent years the science of the
abstract individual mind. Each worker aimed at rendering by the aid
of introspection an analytic description of the stream of his own
consciousness, a consistent classification of the elements or
features that he seemed to discover therein, and some general laws
or rules of the order of succession and conjunction of these
features; postulating in addition some one or more explanatory
principles or active agencies such as ‘the will’ or the desire of
pleasure, the aversion from pain, or ‘the association of ideas,’ to
enable him to account for the flow of the distinguishable elements
of consciousness. The psychology achieved by these studies,
necessary and valuable as they were, was of little help to men who
were struggling with the concrete problems of human life and was
therefore largely ignored by them. But, as I have pointed out in
the Introduction to mySocial
Psychology, those who approached these problems
were generally stimulated to do so by their interest in questions
of right and wrong, in questions of norms and standards of conduct,
the urgency of which demanded immediate answers for the practical
guidance of human life in all its spheres of activity, for the
shaping of laws, institutions, governments, and associations of
every kind; or, as frequently perhaps, for the justification and
defence of standards of conduct, modes of belief, and forms of
institution, which men had learnt to esteem as supremely
good.Thus the political science of Hobbes was the expression of
his attempt to justify the monarchy established by the Tudors and
endangered by the failings of the Stuart kings; while that of Locke
was equally the outcome of his desire to justify the revolution of
1668. Hobbes felt it worth while to preface hismagnum opuson political philosophy
with a fanciful sketch of human nature and of primitive society;
yet, as Mr Gooch remarks, “neither Hobbes nor his contemporaries
knew anything of the actual life of primitive communities[2].” And it may be added that they
knew as little of the foundations of human nature. Again, the
social doctrines of Rousseau, with all their false psychology, were
formulated in order to stir men to revolt against the conditions of
social life then prevalent in Europe. In a similar way, in the
development of all that body of social doctrine that went under the
name of Utilitarianism and which culminated in the political
science and economy of the Manchester School, every step was
prompted by the desire to find theoretical guidance or
justification for rules governing human activity. And, if we go
back to thePoliticsof
Aristotle, we find the normative or regulative aim still more
prominent.Thus, in all the human sciences, we see that the search for
what is has been inextricably confused with and hampered by the
effort to show what ought to be; and the further back we go in
their history, the more does the normative point of view
predominate. They all begin in the effort to describe what ought to
be; and incidentally give some more or less fallacious or fantastic
account of what is, merely in order to support the normative
doctrines. And, as we trace their history forward towards the
present time, we find the positive element coming more and more to
the front, until it tends to preponderate over and even completely
to supplant the normative aim. Thus even in Ethics there is now
perceptible in some quarters a tendency to repudiate the normative
standpoint. All the social sciences have, then, begun their work at
what, from the strictly logical point of view, was the wrong end;
instead of first securing a basis of positive science and then
building up the normative doctrines upon that basis, they have
advanced by repeatedly going backwards towards what should have
been their foundations. Now the most important part of the positive
basis of the social sciences is psychology; we find accordingly the
social sciences at first ignoring psychology and then gradually
working back to it; they became gradually more psychological and,
in proportion as they did so, they became more valuable. Modern
writers on these topics fall into two classes; those who have
attempted to work upon a psychological foundation, and those who
have ignored or denied the need of any such basis. The earlier
efforts of the former kind, among which we may reckon those of Adam
Smith, Bentham, and the Mills, although they greatly influenced
legislation and practice in general, have nevertheless brought the
psychological method into some disrepute, because they reasoned
from psychological principles which were unduly simplified and in
fact misleading, notably the famous principle of psychological
hedonism on which they so greatly relied. Their psychology was, in
brief, too abstract; it had not achieved the necessary
concreteness, which only the introduction of the genetic standpoint
and thevue d’ensemblecould
give it. Other writers on the social sciences were content to
ignore the achievements of psychology; but, since they dealt with
the activities of human beings and the products of those
activities, such as laws, institutions and customs, they could
hardly avoid all reference to the human mind and its processes;
they then relied upon the crude unanalysed psychological
conceptions of popular speech; often they went further and,
aspiring to explain the phenomena they described, made vast
assumptions about the constitution and working of the human mind.
Thus, for example, Renan, when he sought to explain some feature of
the history of a nation or society, was in the habit, like many
others, of ascribing it to some peculiar instinct which he
postulated for this particular purpose, such as a political or a
religious instinct or an instinct of subordination or of
organisation. Comte made egoism and altruism the two master forces
of the mind. Sir Henry Maine asserted that “satisfaction and
impatience are the two great sources of political conduct,” and,
after asserting that “no force acting on mankind has been less
carefully examined than Party, and yet none better deserves
examination,” he was content to conclude that “Party is probably
nothing more than a survival and a consequence of the primitive
combativeness of mankind[3].”
More recently Prof. Giddings has discovered the principal force
underlying all human associations inConsciousness
of Kind. Butler and the intuitive moralists
postulated ‘conscience’ or moral sense as something innately
present in the souls of men; while the creators of the classical
school of political economy were for the most part content to
assume that man is a purely rational being who always intelligently
pursues his own best interest, a false premise from which they
deduced some conclusions that have not withstood the test of time.
Similar vague assumptions may be found in almost every work on the
social sciences,—all illustrating the need for a psychology more
concrete than the older individual psychology, as a basis for these
sciences, a positive science, not of some hypothetical Robinson
Crusoe, but of the mental life of men as it actually unfolds itself
in the families, tribes, nations, societies of all sorts, that make
up the human world.The general growth of interest in genetic problems,
stimulated so greatly by the work of Darwin, turned the attention
of psychologists to the problem of the genesis of the developed
human mind,—the problem of its evolution in the race and its
development in the individual. Then it at once became apparent that
both these processes are essentially social; that they involve, and
at every step are determined by, interactions between the
individual and his social environment; that, while the growth of
the individual mind is moulded by the mental forces of the society
in which it grows up, those forces are in turn the products of the
interplay of the minds composing the society; that, therefore, we
can only understand the life of individuals and the life of
societies, if we consider them always in relation to one another.
It was realised that each man is an individual only in an
incomplete sense; that he is but a unit in a vast system of vital
and spiritual forces which, expressing themselves in the form of
human societies, are working towards ends which no man can foresee;
a unit whose chief function it is to transmit these forces
unimpaired, which can change or add to them only in infinitesimal
degree, and which, therefore, has but little significance and
cannot be accounted for when considered in abstraction from that
system. It became clear that the play of this system of forces at
any moment of history is predominantly determined by conditions
which are themselves the products of an immensely long course of
evolution, conditions which have been produced by the mental
activities of countless generations and which are but very little
modified by the members of society living at any one time; so that,
as has been said, society consists of the dead as well as of the
living, and the part of the living in determining its life is but
insignificant as compared with the part of the dead.Any psychology that recognises these facts and attempts to
display the reciprocal influences of the individual and the society
in which he plays his part may be called Social Psychology.
Collective or Group Psychology is, then, a part of this larger
field. It has to study the mental life of societies of all kinds;
and such understanding of the group life as it can achieve has then
to be used by Social Psychology in rendering more concrete and
complete our understanding of the individual life.Group Psychology itself consists properly of two parts, that
which is concerned to discover the most general principles of group
life, and that which applies these principles to the study of
particular kinds and examples of group life. The former is
logically prior to the second; though in practice it is hardly
possible to keep them wholly apart. The present volume is concerned
chiefly with the former branch. Only when the general principles of
group life have been applied to the understanding of particular
societies, of nations and the manifold system of groups within the
nation, will it be possible for Social Psychology to return upon
the individual life and give of it an adequate account in all its
concrete fulness.The nature of Group Psychology may be illustrated by
reference to Herbert Spencer’s conception of sociology. Spencer
pointed out that, if you set out to build a stable pile of solid
bodies of a certain shape, the kind of structure resulting is
determined by the shapes and properties of these units, that for
example, if the units are spheres, there are only very few stable
forms which the pile can assume. The same is true, he said, of such
physical processes as crystallisation; the form and properties of
the whole or aggregate are determined by the properties of the
units. He maintained with less plausibility that the same holds
good of animal and vegetable forms and of the elements of which
they are composed. And he went on to argue that, in like manner,
the structure and properties of a society are determined by the
properties of the units, the individual human beings, of which it
is composed.This last proposition is true in a very partial sense only.
For the aggregate which is a society has, in virtue of its past
history, positive qualities which it does not derive from the units
which compose it at any one time; and in virtue of these qualities
it acts upon its units in a manner very different from that in
which the units as such interact with one another. Further, each
unit, when it becomes a member of a group, displays properties or
modes of reaction which it does not display, which remain latent or
potential only, so long as it remains outside that group. It is
possible, therefore, to discover these potentialities of the units
only by studying them as elements in the life of the whole. That is
to say, the aggregate which is a society has a certain
individuality, is a true whole which in great measure determines
the nature and the modes of activity of its parts; it is an organic
whole. The society has a mental life which is not the mere sum of
the mental lives of its units existing as independent units; and a
complete knowledge of the units, if and in so far as they could be
known as isolated units, would not enable us to deduce the nature
of the life of the whole, in the way that is implied by Spencer’s
analogies.Since, then, the social aggregate has a collective mental
life, which is not merely the sum of the mental lives of its units,
it may be contended that a society not only enjoys a collective
mental life but also has a collective mind or, as some prefer to
say, a collective soul.The tasks of Group Psychology are, then, to examine the
conception of the collective or group mind, in order to determine
whether and in what sense this is a valid conception; to display
the general principles of collective mental life which are
incapable of being deduced from the laws of the mental life of
isolated individuals; to distinguish the principal types of
collective mental life or group mind; to describe the peculiarities
of those types and as far as possible to account for them. More
shortly, Group Psychology has, first, to establish the general
principles of group life (this is general collective psychology);
secondly, it has to apply these principles in the endeavour to
understand particular examples of group life. Group Psychology,
thus conceived, meets at the outset a difficulty which stands in
the way of every attempt of psychology to leave the narrow field of
highly abstract individual psychology. It finds the ground already
staked out and occupied by the representatives of another science,
who are inclined to resent its intrusion as an encroachment on
their rights. The science which claims to have occupied the field
of Group Psychology is Sociology; and it is of some importance that
the claims of these sciences should be reconciled, so that they may
live and work harmoniously together. I have no desire to claim for
Group Psychology the whole province of Sociology. As I conceive it,
that province is much wider than that of Group Psychology.
Sociology is essentially a science which has to take a
comprehensive and synthetic view of the life of mankind, and has to
accept and make use of the conclusions of many other more special
sciences, of which psychology, and especially Group Psychology, is
for it perhaps the most important. But other special sciences have
very important if less intimate contributions to make to it. Thus,
if it be true that great civilisations have decayed owing to
changes of climate of their habitats, or owing to the introduction
of such diseases as malaria into them, then Climatology and
Epidemiology have their contributions to make to Sociology. If
peculiarities of diet or the crossing of racial stocks may
profoundly affect the vigour of peoples, Physiology must have its
say. General biology and the science of Genetics are bringing to
light much that must be incorporated in Sociology. Economics,
although needing to be treated far more psychologically than it
commonly has been, has its special contribution to make. These are
only a few illustrations of the fact that the field of Sociology is
very much wider and more general than that of Group Psychology,
however important to it the conclusions of the narrower science may
be.In this book it will be maintained that the conception of a
group mind is useful and therefore valid; and, since this notion
has already excited some opposition and criticism and is one that
requires very careful definition, some attempt to define and
justify it may usefully be made at the outset; though the completer
justification is the substance of the whole book. Some writers have
assumed the reality of what is called the ‘collective
consciousness’ of a society, meaning thereby a unitary
consciousness of the society over and above that of the individuals
comprised within it. This conception is examined in Chapter II and
provisionally rejected. But it is maintained that a society, when
it enjoys a long life and becomes highly organised, acquires a
structure and qualities which are largely independent of the
qualities of the individuals who enter into its composition and
take part for a brief time in its life. It becomes an organised
system of forces which has a life of its own, tendencies of its
own, a power of moulding all its component individuals, and a power
of perpetuating itself as a self-identical system, subject only to
slow and gradual change.In an earlier work, in which I have sketched in outline the
program of psychology[4], I
wrote: “When the student of behaviour has learnt from the various
departments of psychology ... all that they can teach him of the
structure, genesis, and modes of operation of the individual mind,
a large field still awaits his exploration. If we put aside as
unproven such speculations as that touched on at the end of the
foregoing chapter (the view of James that the human mind can enter
into an actual union or communion with the divine mind) and refuse
to admit any modes of communication or influence between minds
other than through the normal channels of sense-perception and
bodily movement, we must nevertheless recognise the existence in a
certain sense of over-individual or collective minds. We may fairly
define a mind as an organised system of mental or purposive forces;
and, in the sense so defined, every highly organised human society
may properly be said to possess a collective mind. For the
collective actions which constitute the history of any such society
are conditioned by an organisation which can only be described in
terms of mind, and which yet is not comprised within the mind of
any individual; the society is rather constituted by the system of
relations obtaining between the individual minds which are its
units of composition. Under any given circumstances the actions of
the society are, or may be, very different from the mere sum of the
actions with which its several members would react to the situation
in the absence of the system of relations which render them a
society; or, in other words, the thinking and acting of each man,
in so far as he thinks and acts as a member of a society, are very
different from his thinking and acting as an isolated
individual.”This passage has been cited by the author of a notable work
on Sociology[5], and made by
him the text of a polemic against the conception of the group mind.
He writes: “This passage contains two arguments in favour of the
hypothesis of super-individual ‘collective’ minds, neither of which
can stand examination. The ‘definition’ of a mind as ‘an organised
system of mental or purposive forces’ is totally inadequate. When
we speak of the mind of an individual we mean something more than
this. The mind of each of us has a unity other than that of such a
system.” But I doubt whether Mr Maciver could explain exactly what
kind of unity it is that he postulates. Is it the unity of soul
substance? I have myself contended at some length that this is a
necessary postulate or hypothesis[6], but I do not suppose that
Maciver accepts or intends to refer to this conception. Is it the
unity of consciousness or of self-consciousness? Then the answer is
that this unity is by no means a general and established function
of the individual mind; modern studies of the disintegration of
personality have shown this to be a questionable assumption,
undermined by the many facts of normal and abnormal psychology best
resumed under Dr Morton Prince’s term
‘co-consciousness.’The individual mind is a system of purposive forces, but the
system is by no means always a harmonious system; it is but too apt
to be the scene of fierce conflicts which sometimes (in the graver
psychoneuroses) result in the rupture and disintegration of the
system. I do not know how otherwise we are to describe the
individual mind than as a system of mental forces; and, until
Maciver succeeds in showing in what other sense he conceives it to
have “a unity other than that of such a system,” his objection
cannot be seriously entertained. He asks, of the alleged collective
mind: “Does the system so created think and will and feel and
act[7]?” My answer, as set
out in the following pages, is that it does all of these things. He
asks further: “If a number of minds construct by their
interactivity an organisation ‘which can only be described in terms
of mind,’ must we ascribe to the construction the very nature of
the forces which constructed it?” To this I reply—my point is that
the individual minds which enter into the structure of the group
mind at any moment of its life do not construct it; rather, as they
come to reflective self-consciousness, they find themselves already
members of the system, moulded by it, sharing in its activities,
influenced by it at every moment in every thought and feeling and
action in ways which they can neither fully understand nor escape
from, struggle as they may to free themselves from its infinitely
subtle and multitudinous forces. And this system, as Maciver
himself forcibly insists in another connection, does not consist of
relations that exist external to and independently of the things
related, namely the minds of individuals; it consists of the same
stuff as the individual minds, its threads and parts lie within
these minds; but the parts in the several individual minds
reciprocally imply and complement one another and together make up
the system which consists wholly of them; and therefore, as I
wrote, they can “only be described in terms of mind.” Any society
is literally a more or less organised mental system; the stuff of
which it consists is mental stuff; the forces that operate within
it are mental forces. Maciver argues further: “Social organisations
occur of every kind and every degree of universality. If England
has a collective mind, why not Birmingham and why not each of its
wards? If a nation has a collective mind, so also have a church and
a trade union. And we shall have collective minds that are parts of
greater collective minds, and collective minds that intersect other
collective minds.” By this my withers are quite unwrung. What
degree of organisation is necessary before a society can properly
be said to enjoy collective mental life or have a group mind is a
question of degree; and the exponent of the group mind is under no
obligation to return a precise answer to this question. My
contention is that the most highly organised groups display
collective mental life in a way which justifies the conception of
the group mind, and that we shall be helped to understand
collective life in these most complex and difficult forms by
studying it in the simpler less elaborated groups where the
conception of a group mind is less clearly applicable. As regards
the overlapping and intersection of groups and the consequent
difficulty of assigning the limits of groups whose unity is implied
by the term group mind, I would point out that this difficulty
arises only in connexion with the lower forms of group life and
that a parallel difficulty is presented by the lower forms of
animal life. Is Maciver acquainted with the organisation of a
sponge, or of the so-called coral ‘insect,’ or with that of the
Portuguese man-o’-war? Would he deny the unity of a human being, or
refuse to acknowledge his possession of a mind, because in these
lower organisms the limits of the unit are hard or impossible to
assign? Maciver goes on: “The second argument is an obvious
fallacy. If each man thinks and acts differently as a member of a
crowd or association and as an individual standing out of any such
immediate relation to his fellows, it is still each who thinks and
acts; the new determinations are determinations still of individual
minds as they are influenced by aggregation.... But this is merely
an extreme instance of the obvious fact that every mind is
influenced by every kind of environment. To posit a
super-individual mind because individual minds are altered by their
relations to one another (as indeed they are altered by their
relations to physical conditions) is surely gratuitous[8].” To this I reply—the environment
which influences the individual in his life as a member of an
organised group is neither the sum of his fellow members as
individuals, nor is it something that has other than a mental
existence. It is the organised group as such, which exists only or
chiefly in the persons of those composing it, but which does not
exist in the mind of any one of them, and which operates upon each
so powerfully just because it is something indefinitely greater,
more powerful, more comprehensive than the mere sum of those
individuals. Maciver feels that “it is important to clear out of
the way this misleading doctrine of super-individual minds
corresponding to social or communal organisations and activities,”
and therefore goes on to say that “there is no more a great
‘collective’ mind beyond the individual minds in society than there
is a great ‘collective’ tree beyond all the individual trees in
nature. A collection of trees is a wood, and that we can study as a
unity; so an aggregation of men is a society, a much more
determinate unity; but a collection of trees is not a collective
tree, and neither is a collection of persons or minds a collective
person or mind. We can speak of qualities of tree in abstraction
from any particular tree, and we can speak of qualities of mind as
such, or of some particular kind of mind in relation to some type
of situation. Yet in so doing we are simply considering the
characteristic of like elements of individual minds, as we might
consider the characteristic or like elements discoverable in
individual trees and kinds of trees. To conceive because of these
identities, a ‘collective’ mind as existingbesidethose of individuals or a
collective tree beside the variant examples is to run against the
wall of the Idea theory.” Now, I am not proposing to commit myself
to this last-named theory. It is not because minds have much in
common with one another that I speak of the collective mind, but
because the group as such is more than the sum of the individuals,
has its own life proceeding according to laws of group life, which
are not the laws of individual life, and because its peculiar group
life reacts upon and profoundly modifies the lives of the
individuals. I would not call a forest a collective tree; but I
would maintain that in certain respects a forest, a wood, or a
copse, has in a rudimentary way a collective life. Thus the forest
remains the same forest though, after a hundred or a thousand
years, all its constituent trees may be different individuals; and
again the forest as a whole may and does modify the life of each
tree, as by attracting moisture, protecting from violent and cold
winds, harbouring various plants and animals which affect the
trees, and so on.But I will cite an eloquent passage from a recent work on
sociology in support of my view. “The bonds of society are in the
members of society, and not outside them. It is the memories,
traditions, and beliefs of each which make up the social memories,
traditions and beliefs. Society like the kingdom of God is within
us. Within us, within each of us, and yet greater than the thoughts
and understandings of any of us. For the social thoughts and
feelings and willings of each, the socialised mind of each, with
the complex scheme of his relation to the social world, is no mere
reproduction of the social thoughts and feelings and willings of
the rest. Unity and difference here too weave their eternal web,
the greater social scheme which none of us who are part of it can
ever see in its entirety, but whose infinite subtlety and harmony
we may more and more comprehend and admire. As a community grows in
civilisation and culture, its traditions are no longer clear and
definite ways of thinking, its usages are no longer uniform, its
spirit is no longer to be summed up in a few phrases. But the
spirit and tradition of a people become no less real in becoming
more complex. Each member no longer embodies the whole tradition,
but it is because each embodies some part of a greater tradition to
which the freely-working individuality of each contributes. In this
sense the spirit of a people, though existing only in the
individual members, more and more surpasses the measure of any
individual mind. Again, the social tradition is expressed through
institutions and records more permanent than the short-lived
members of community. These institutions and records are as it were
stored social values (just as, in particular, books may be called
stored social knowledge),in themselves
nothing, no part of the social mind, but the
instruments of the communication of traditions from member to
member, as also from the dead past to the living present. In this
way too, with the increase of these stored values, of which members
realise parts but none the whole, the spirit of a people more and
more surpasses the measure of any individual mind. It is these
social forces within and without, working in the minds of
individuals whose own social inheritance is an essential part of
their individuality, stored in the institutions which they maintain
from the past or establish in the present, that mould the communal
spirit of the successive generations. In this sense too a community
may be called greater than its members who exist at any one time,
since the community itself marches out of the past into the
present, and its members at any time are part of a great
succession, themselves first moulded by communal forces before they
become, so moulded, the active determinants of its future
moulding.” An admirable statement! “The greater social scheme which
none of us can see in its entirety”—“the spirit of a people” which
“more and more surpasses the measure of any individual mind”—“the
communal spirit of the successive generations”—“the community”
which is “greater than its members who exist at any one time”; all
these are alternative designations of that organised system of
mental forces which exists over and above, though not independently
of, the individuals in each of whom some fragment of it is embodied
and which is the group mind. And the writer of this statement is Mr
R. M. Maciver; the passage occurs in the section of his book
designed to “clear out of the way this misleading doctrine of
super-individual minds.” In the same section he goes on to say that
“every association, every organised group, may and does have rights
and obligations which are not the rights and obligations of any or
all of its members taken distributively but only of the association
acting as an organised unity.... As a unity the association may
become a ‘juristic person,’ a ‘corporation,’ and from the legal
standpoint the character of unity so conceived is very
important.... The ‘juristic person’ is a realunity, and therefore more than
apersona ficta, but the
reality it possesses is of a totally different order of being from
that of the persons who establish it.” But, perversely as it seems
to me, Maciver adds “the unity of which we are thinking is not
mechanic or organic or even psychic.” I cannot but think that, in
thus denying the organic and psychic nature of this unity, Maciver
is under the influence of that unfortunate and still prevalent way
of thinking of the psychic as identical with the conscious which
has given endless trouble in psychology; because it has prompted
the hopeless attempt, constantly renewed, to describe the structure
and organisation of the mind in terms of conscious stuff, ignoring
the all-important distinction between mental activity, which is
sometimes, though perhaps not always, consciousness, and mental
structure which is not. The structure and organisation of the
spirit of the community is in every respect as purely mental or
psychic as is the structure and organisation of the individual
mind.Maciver very properly goes on to bring his conclusions to the
pragmatic test, the test of practical results. He writes: “These
false analogies ... are the sources of that most misleading
antithesis which we draw between the individual and society, as
though society were somehow other than its individuals.... Analyse
these misleading analogies, and in the revelation of their falsity
there is revealed also the falsity of this essential opposition of
individual and society. Properly understood, the interests of ‘the
individual’ are the interests of society[9].” But is it true that the
interests of the individual are identical with the interests of
society? Obviously not. We have only to think of the condemned
criminal; of the mentally defective to whom every enlightened
society should deny the right of procreation; of the young soldier
who sacrifices his health, his limbs, his eyesight, or his life,
and perhaps the welfare of his loved ones, in serving his country.
It is true that the progress of society is essentially an
approximation towards an ideal state in which this identification
would be completed; but that is an ideal which can never be
absolutely realised. Nor is it even true that the interests of
society are identical with the interests of the majority of its
members existing at any one time. It is, I think, highly probable
that, if any great modern nation should unanimously and
wholeheartedly embark upon a thorough-going scheme of
state-socialism, the interests of the vast majority of individuals
would be greatly promoted; they would be enabled to live more
prosperously and comfortably with greater leisure and opportunity
for the higher forms of activity. It is, however, equally probable
that the higher interests of the nation would be gravely
endangered, that it would enter upon a period of increasing
stagnation and diminishing vitality and, after a few generations
had passed away, would have slipped far down the slope which has
led all great societies of the past to destruction.The question may be considered in relation to the German
nation. As will be pointed out in a later chapter, the structure of
that nation was, before the Great War, a menace to European
civilisation. If the Germans had succeeded in their aims and had
conquered Europe or the world, their individual interests would
have been vastly promoted; they would have enjoyed immense material
prosperity and a proud consciousness of having been chosen by God
to rule the rest of mankind for their good. And this would have
confirmed the nation in all its vices and would have finally
crushed out of it all its potentialities for developing into a
well-organised nation of the higher type, fitted to play an
honourable part in the future evolution of mankind. The same truth
appears if we consider the problem of the responsibility of the
German nation for the War. So long as that people might retain its
former organisation, which, I repeat, rendered it a menace to the
civilisation and culture of the whole world, its antagonists could
only treat it as a criminal and an outlaw to be repressed at all
costs and punished and kept down with the utmost severity. But, if
it should achieve a new organisation, one which will give
preponderance to the better and saner elements and traditions still
preserved within it, then, although it will consist of the same
individuals in the main, it will have become a new or at least a
transformed nation, one with which the other nations could enter
into normal relations of amity or at least of mutual toleration,
one which could be admitted to a place in the greater society which
the League of Nations is to become. In other words, the same
population would in virtue of a changed organisation, have become a
different nation.Although Maciver, in making his attack upon the conception of
the group mind, has done me the honour to choose me as its
exponent, I do not stand alone in maintaining it. I am a little shy
of citing in its support the philosophers of the school of German
‘idealism,’ because, as I have indicated in the Preface, I have
little sympathy with that school. Yet, though one may disapprove of
the methods and of most of the conclusions of a school of thought,
one may still adduce in support of one’s opinion such of its
principles as seem to be well founded. I may, then, remind the
reader that the conception of the State as a super-individual, a
superhuman quasi-divine personality, is the central conception of
the political philosophy of German ‘idealism.’ That conception has,
no doubt, played a considerable part in bringing upon Europe its
present disaster. It was an instance of one of those philosophical
ideas which claim to be the product of pure reason, yet in reality
are adopted for the purpose of justifying and furthering some
already existing interest or institution. In this case the
institution in question was the Prussian state and those, Hegel and
the rest, who set up this doctrine were servants of that state.
They made of their doctrine an instrument for the suppression of
individuality which greatly aided in producing the servile
condition of the German people. Yet the distortions and
exaggerations of the political philosophy of German ‘idealism’
should not prejudice us against the germ of truth which it
contains; and the more enlightened British disciples of this
school, from T.H. Green onwards, have sought with much success to
winnow the grain from the chaff of the doctrine; and I cannot
adduce better support for the conception of the group mind than the
sentences in which a recent English writer, a sympathetic student
of German ‘idealism,’ sums up the results of this winnowing
process[10]. Discussing the
deficiencies of the individualist philosophy of the English
utilitarian school, he writes: “Not a modification of the old
Benthamite premises, but a new philosophy was needed; and that
philosophy was provided by the idealist school, of which Green is
the greatest representative. That school drew its inspiration
immediately from Kant and Hegel, and ultimately from the old Greek
philosophy of the city-state. The vital relation between the life
of the individual and the life of the community, which alone gives
the individual worth and significance, because it alone gives him
the power of full moral development; the dependence of the
individual, for all his rights and for all his liberty, on his
membership of the community; the correlative duty of the community
to guarantee to the individual all his rights (in other words, all
the conditions necessary for his, and therefore for its own, full
moral development)—these were the premisses of the new philosophy.
That philosophy could satisfy the new needs of social progress,
because it refused to worship a supposed individual liberty which
was proving destructive of the real liberty of the vast majority,
and preferred to emphasise the moral well-being and betterment of
the whole community, and to conceive of each of its members as
attaining his own well-being and betterment in and through the
community. Herein lay, or seemed to lie, a revolution of ideas.
Instead of starting from a central individual, to whom the social
system is supposed to be adjusted, the idealist starts from a
central social system, in which the individual must find his
appointed orbit of duty. But after all the revolution is only a
restoration; and what is restored is simply theRepublicof Plato[11].” The same writer reminds us
that “both Plato and Hegel thus imply the idea of a moral
organism”; and he adds, “It is this conception of a moral organism
which Bradley urges. It is implied in daily experience, and it is
the only explanation of that experience. ‘In fact, what we call an
individual man is what he is because of and by virtue of community,
and communities are not mere names, but something real.’ Already at
birth the child is what he is in virtue of communities: he has
something of the family character, something of the national
character, something of the civilised character which comes from
human society. As he grows, the community in which he lives pours
itself into his being in the language he learns and the social
atmosphere he breathes, so that the content of his being implies in
its every fibre relations of community. He is what he is by
including in his essence the relations of the social State.... And
regarding the State as a system, in which many spheres (the family,
for instance) are subordinated to one sphere, and all the
particular actions of individuals are subordinated to their various
spheres, we may call it a moral organism, a systematic whole
informed by a common purpose or function. As such it has an outer
side—a body of institutions; it has an inner side—a soul or spirit
which sustains that body. And since it is a moral organism—since,
that is to say, its parts are themselves conscious moral
agents—that spirit resides in those parts and lives in their
consciousness. In such an organism—and this is where it differs
from an animal organism, and why we have to use the word moral—the
parts are conscious: they know themselves in their position as
parts of the whole, and they therefore know the whole of which they
are parts. So far as they have such knowledge, and a will based
upon it, so far is the moral organism self-conscious and
self-willing.... Thus, on the one hand, we must recognise that the
State lives; that there is a nation’s soul, self-conscious in its
citizens; and that to each citizen this living soul assigns his
field of accomplishment[12].”
On a later page of the same book we read—“All the institutions of a
country, so far as they are effective, are not only products of
thought and creations of mind: theyarethought, and theyaremind. Otherwise we have a building
without a tenant, and a body without a mind. An Oxford college is
not a group of buildings, though common speech gives that name to
such a group: it is a group of men. But it is not a group of men in
the sense of a group of bodies in propinquity: it is a group of men
in the sense of a group of minds. That group of minds, in virtue of
the common substance of an uniting idea, is itself a group-mind.
There is no group-mind existing apart from the minds of the members
of the group; the group-mind only exists in the minds of its
members. But nevertheless it exists. There is a college mind, just
as there is a Trade Union mind, or even a ‘public mind’ of the
whole community; and we are all conscious of such a mind as
something that exists in and along with the separate minds of the
members, and over and above any sum of those minds created by mere
addition[13].”The political philosophers of the idealist school have not
stood alone in recognising the reality of the group mind. Some of
the lawyers, notably Maitland, have arrived at a very similar
doctrine; and I cannot better summarise their conclusions than
Barker has done in the following passage in the book from which I
have already cited so freely. “The new doctrine,” he writes, “runs
somewhat as follows. No permanent group, permanently organised for
a durable object, can be regarded as a mere sum of persons, whose
union, to have any rights or duties, must receive a legal
confirmation. Permanent groups are themselves persons,
group-persons, with a group-will of their own and a permanent
character of their own; and they have become group-persons of
themselves, without any creative act of the State. In a word,
group-persons are real persons; and just because they are so, and
possess such attributes of persons as will and character, they
cannot have been made by the State[14].”I am not alone, then, in postulating the reality of the group
mind. And I am glad to be able to cite evidence of this, because I
know well that very many readers may at first find themselves
repelled by this notion of a group mind, and that some of them will
incline to regard it as the fantastic fad of an academic
crank.I would say at once that the crucial point of difference
between my own view of the group mind and that of the German
‘idealist’ school (at least in its more extreme representatives) is
that I repudiate, provisionally at least, as an unverifiable
hypothesis the conception of a collective or super-individual
consciousness, somehow comprising the consciousness of the
individuals composing the group. I have examined this conception in
the following chapter and have stated my grounds for rejecting it.
The difference of practical conclusions arising from this
difference of theory must obviously be very great.Several books dealing with collective psychology have been
published in recent years. Of these perhaps the most notable are G.
le Bon’sPsychology of the Crowd, hisEvolution psychologique des
peuples; Sighele’sLa foule
criminelle; thePsychologie
collectiveof Dr A. A. Marie; and Alfred
Fouillée’sLa Science sociale
contemporaine